您的位置 : 首页 > 英文著作
Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER IV - IDEALISM
Bertrand Russell
下载:Problems of Philosophy.txt
本书全文检索:
       _ CHAPTER IV - IDEALISM
       The word 'idealism' is used by different philosophers in somewhat
       different senses. We shall understand by it the doctrine that
       whatever exists, or at any rate whatever can be known to exist, must
       be in some sense mental. This doctrine, which is very widely held
       among philosophers, has several forms, and is advocated on several
       different grounds. The doctrine is so widely held, and so interesting
       in itself, that even the briefest survey of philosophy must give some
       account of it.
       Those who are unaccustomed to philosophical speculation may be
       inclined to dismiss such a doctrine as obviously absurd. There is no
       doubt that common sense regards tables and chairs and the sun and moon
       and material objects generally as something radically different from
       minds and the contents of minds, and as having an existence which
       might continue if minds ceased. We think of matter as having existed
       long before there were any minds, and it is hard to think of it as a
       mere product of mental activity. But whether true or false, idealism
       is not to be dismissed as obviously absurd.
       We have seen that, even if physical objects do have an independent
       existence, they must differ very widely from sense-data, and can only
       have a _correspondence_ with sense-data, in the same sort of way in
       which a catalogue has a correspondence with the things catalogued.
       Hence common sense leaves us completely in the dark as to the true
       intrinsic nature of physical objects, and if there were good reason to
       regard them as mental, we could not legitimately reject this opinion
       merely because it strikes us as strange. The truth about physical
       objects _must_ be strange. It may be unattainable, but if any
       philosopher believes that he has attained it, the fact that what he
       offers as the truth is strange ought not to be made a ground of
       objection to his opinion.
       The grounds on which idealism is advocated are generally grounds
       derived from the theory of knowledge, that is to say, from a
       discussion of the conditions which things must satisfy in order that
       we may be able to know them. The first serious attempt to establish
       idealism on such grounds was that of Bishop Berkeley. He proved
       first, by arguments which were largely valid, that our sense-data
       cannot be supposed to have an existence independent of us, but must
       be, in part at least, 'in' the mind, in the sense that their existence
       would not continue if there were no seeing or hearing or touching or
       smelling or tasting. So far, his contention was almost certainly
       valid, even if some of his arguments were not so. But he went on to
       argue that sense-data were the only things of whose existence our
       perceptions could assure us; and that to be known is to be 'in' a
       mind, and therefore to be mental. Hence he concluded that nothing can
       ever be known except what is in some mind, and that whatever is known
       without being in my mind must be in some other mind.
       In order to understand his argument, it is necessary to understand his
       use of the word 'idea'. He gives the name 'idea' to anything which is
       _immediately_ known, as, for example, sense-data are known. Thus a
       particular colour which we see is an idea; so is a voice which we
       hear, and so on. But the term is not wholly confined to sense-data.
       There will also be things remembered or imagined, for with such things
       also we have immediate acquaintance at the moment of remembering or
       imagining. All such immediate data he calls 'ideas'.
       He then proceeds to consider common objects, such as a tree, for
       instance. He shows that all we know immediately when we 'perceive'
       the tree consists of ideas in his sense of the word, and he argues
       that there is not the slightest ground for supposing that there is
       anything real about the tree except what is perceived. Its being, he
       says, consists in being perceived: in the Latin of the schoolmen its
       '_esse_' is '_percipi_'. He fully admits that the tree must continue
       to exist even when we shut our eyes or when no human being is near it.
       But this continued existence, he says, is due to the fact that God
       continues to perceive it; the 'real' tree, which corresponds to what
       we called the physical object, consists of ideas in the mind of God,
       ideas more or less like those we have when we see the tree, but
       differing in the fact that they are permanent in God's mind so long as
       the tree continues to exist. All our perceptions, according to him,
       consist in a partial participation in God's perceptions, and it is
       because of this participation that different people see more or less
       the same tree. Thus apart from minds and their ideas there is nothing
       in the world, nor is it possible that anything else should ever be
       known, since whatever is known is necessarily an idea.
       There are in this argument a good many fallacies which have been
       important in the history of philosophy, and which it will be as well
       to bring to light. In the first place, there is a confusion
       engendered by the use of the word 'idea'. We think of an idea as
       essentially something in somebody's mind, and thus when we are told
       that a tree consists entirely of ideas, it is natural to suppose that,
       if so, the tree must be entirely in minds. But the notion of being
       'in' the mind is ambiguous. We speak of bearing a person in mind, not
       meaning that the person is in our minds, but that a thought of him is
       in our minds. When a man says that some business he had to arrange
       went clean out of his mind, he does not mean to imply that the
       business itself was ever in his mind, but only that a thought of the
       business was formerly in his mind, but afterwards ceased to be in his
       mind. And so when Berkeley says that the tree must be in our minds if
       we can know it, all that he really has a right to say is that a
       thought of the tree must be in our minds. To argue that the tree
       itself must be in our minds is like arguing that a person whom we bear
       in mind is himself in our minds. This confusion may seem too gross to
       have been really committed by any competent philosopher, but various
       attendant circumstances rendered it possible. In order to see how it
       was possible, we must go more deeply into the question as to the
       nature of ideas.
       Before taking up the general question of the nature of ideas, we must
       disentangle two entirely separate questions which arise concerning
       sense-data and physical objects. We saw that, for various reasons of
       detail, Berkeley was right in treating the sense-data which constitute
       our perception of the tree as more or less subjective, in the sense
       that they depend upon us as much as upon the tree, and would not exist
       if the tree were not being perceived. But this is an entirely
       different point from the one by which Berkeley seeks to prove that
       whatever can be immediately known must be in a mind. For this purpose
       arguments of detail as to the dependence of sense-data upon us are
       useless. It is necessary to prove, generally, that by being known,
       things are shown to be mental. This is what Berkeley believes himself
       to have done. It is this question, and not our previous question as
       to the difference between sense-data and the physical object, that
       must now concern us.
       Taking the word 'idea' in Berkeley's sense, there are two quite
       distinct things to be considered whenever an idea is before the mind.
       There is on the one hand the thing of which we are aware--say the
       colour of my table--and on the other hand the actual awareness itself,
       the mental act of apprehending the thing. The mental act is
       undoubtedly mental, but is there any reason to suppose that the thing
       apprehended is in any sense mental? Our previous arguments concerning
       the colour did not prove it to be mental; they only proved that its
       existence depends upon the relation of our sense organs to the
       physical object--in our case, the table. That is to say, they proved
       that a certain colour will exist, in a certain light, if a normal eye
       is placed at a certain point relatively to the table. They did not
       prove that the colour is in the mind of the percipient.
       Berkeley's view, that obviously the colour must be in the mind, seems
       to depend for its plausibility upon confusing the thing apprehended
       with the act of apprehension. Either of these might be called an
       'idea'; probably either would have been called an idea by Berkeley.
       The act is undoubtedly in the mind; hence, when we are thinking of the
       act, we readily assent to the view that ideas must be in the mind.
       Then, forgetting that this was only true when ideas were taken as acts
       of apprehension, we transfer the proposition that 'ideas are in the
       mind' to ideas in the other sense, i.e. to the things apprehended by
       our acts of apprehension. Thus, by an unconscious equivocation, we
       arrive at the conclusion that whatever we can apprehend must be in our
       minds. This seems to be the true analysis of Berkeley's argument, and
       the ultimate fallacy upon which it rests.
       This question of the distinction between act and object in our
       apprehending of things is vitally important, since our whole power of
       acquiring knowledge is bound up with it. The faculty of being
       acquainted with things other than itself is the main characteristic of
       a mind. Acquaintance with objects essentially consists in a relation
       between the mind and something other than the mind; it is this that
       constitutes the mind's power of knowing things. If we say that the
       things known must be in the mind, we are either unduly limiting the
       mind's power of knowing, or we are uttering a mere tautology. We are
       uttering a mere tautology if we mean by '_in_ the mind' the same as by
       '_before_ the mind', i.e. if we mean merely being apprehended by the
       mind. But if we mean this, we shall have to admit that what, _in this
       sense_, is in the mind, may nevertheless be not mental. Thus when we
       realize the nature of knowledge, Berkeley's argument is seen to be
       wrong in substance as well as in form, and his grounds for supposing
       that 'ideas'--i.e. the objects apprehended--must be mental, are found
       to have no validity whatever. Hence his grounds in favour of idealism
       may be dismissed. It remains to see whether there are any other
       grounds.
       It is often said, as though it were a self-evident truism, that we
       cannot know that anything exists which we do not know. It is inferred
       that whatever can in any way be relevant to our experience must be at
       least capable of being known by us; whence it follows that if matter
       were essentially something with which we could not become acquainted,
       matter would be something which we could not know to exist, and which
       could have for us no importance whatever. It is generally also
       implied, for reasons which remain obscure, that what can have no
       importance for us cannot be real, and that therefore matter, if it is
       not composed of minds or of mental ideas, is impossible and a mere
       chimaera.
       To go into this argument fully at our present stage would be
       impossible, since it raises points requiring a considerable
       preliminary discussion; but certain reasons for rejecting the argument
       may be noticed at once. To begin at the end: there is no reason why
       what cannot have any _practical_ importance for us should not be real.
       It is true that, if _theoretical_ importance is included, everything
       real is of _some_ importance to us, since, as persons desirous of
       knowing the truth about the universe, we have some interest in
       everything that the universe contains. But if this sort of interest
       is included, it is not the case that matter has no importance for us,
       provided it exists even if we cannot know that it exists. We can,
       obviously, suspect that it may exist, and wonder whether it does;
       hence it is connected with our desire for knowledge, and has the
       importance of either satisfying or thwarting this desire.
       Again, it is by no means a truism, and is in fact false, that we
       cannot know that anything exists which we do not know. The word
       'know' is here used in two different senses. (1) In its first use it
       is applicable to the sort of knowledge which is opposed to error, the
       sense in which what we know is _true_, the sense which applies to our
       beliefs and convictions, i.e. to what are called _judgements_. In
       this sense of the word we know _that_ something is the case. This
       sort of knowledge may be described as knowledge of _truths_. (2) In
       the second use of the word 'know' above, the word applies to our
       knowledge of _things_, which we may call _acquaintance_. This is the
       sense in which we know sense-data. (The distinction involved is
       roughly that between _savoir_ and _conna”tre_ in French, or between
       _wissen_ and _kennen_ in German.)
       Thus the statement which seemed like a truism becomes, when re-stated,
       the following: 'We can never truly judge that something with which we
       are not acquainted exists.' This is by no means a truism, but on the
       contrary a palpable falsehood. I have not the honour to be acquainted
       with the Emperor of China, but I truly judge that he exists. It may
       be said, of course, that I judge this because of other people's
       acquaintance with him. This, however, would be an irrelevant retort,
       since, if the principle were true, I could not know that any one else
       is acquainted with him. But further: there is no reason why I should
       not know of the existence of something with which nobody is
       acquainted. This point is important, and demands elucidation.
       If I am acquainted with a thing which exists, my acquaintance gives me
       the knowledge that it exists. But it is not true that, conversely,
       whenever I can know that a thing of a certain sort exists, I or some
       one else must be acquainted with the thing. What happens, in cases
       where I have true judgement without acquaintance, is that the thing is
       known to me by _description_, and that, in virtue of some general
       principle, the existence of a thing answering to this description can
       be inferred from the existence of something with which I am
       acquainted. In order to understand this point fully, it will be well
       first to deal with the difference between knowledge by acquaintance
       and knowledge by description, and then to consider what knowledge of
       general principles, if any, has the same kind of certainty as our
       knowledge of the existence of our own experiences. These subjects
       will be dealt with in the following chapters.
        
       ___
       End of CHAPTER IV - IDEALISM
       [Bertrand Russell's essay: The Problems of Philosophy] _