您的位置 : 首页 > 英文著作
Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER XIV - THE LIMITS OF PHILOSOPHICAL KNOWLEDGE
Bertrand Russell
下载:Problems of Philosophy.txt
本书全文检索:
       _ CHAPTER XIV - THE LIMITS OF PHILOSOPHICAL KNOWLEDGE
       In all that we have said hitherto concerning philosophy, we have
       scarcely touched on many matters that occupy a great space in the
       writings of most philosophers. Most philosophers--or, at any rate,
       very many--profess to be able to prove, by _a priori_ metaphysical
       reasoning, such things as the fundamental dogmas of religion, the
       essential rationality of the universe, the illusoriness of matter, the
       unreality of all evil, and so on. There can be no doubt that the hope
       of finding reason to believe such theses as these has been the chief
       inspiration of many life-long students of philosophy. This hope, I
       believe, is vain. It would seem that knowledge concerning the
       universe as a whole is not to be obtained by metaphysics, and that the
       proposed proofs that, in virtue of the laws of logic such and such
       things _must_ exist and such and such others cannot, are not capable
       of surviving a critical scrutiny. In this chapter we shall briefly
       consider the kind of way in which such reasoning is attempted, with a
       view to discovering whether we can hope that it may be valid.
       The great representative, in modern times, of the kind of view which
       we wish to examine, was Hegel (1770-1831). Hegel's philosophy is very
       difficult, and commentators differ as to the true interpretation of
       it. According to the interpretation I shall adopt, which is that of
       many, if not most, of the commentators and has the merit of giving an
       interesting and important type of philosophy, his main thesis is that
       everything short of the Whole is obviously fragmentary, and obviously
       incapable of existing without the complement supplied by the rest of
       the world. Just as a comparative anatomist, from a single bone, sees
       what kind of animal the whole must have been, so the metaphysician,
       according to Hegel, sees, from any one piece of reality, what the
       whole of reality must be--at least in its large outlines. Every
       apparently separate piece of reality has, as it were, hooks which
       grapple it to the next piece; the next piece, in turn, has fresh
       hooks, and so on, until the whole universe is reconstructed. This
       essential incompleteness appears, according to Hegel, equally in the
       world of thought and in the world of things. In the world of thought,
       if we take any idea which is abstract or incomplete, we find, on
       examination, that if we forget its incompleteness, we become involved
       in contradictions; these contradictions turn the idea in question into
       its opposite, or antithesis; and in order to escape, we have to find a
       new, less incomplete idea, which is the synthesis of our original idea
       and its antithesis. This new idea, though less incomplete than the
       idea we started with, will be found, nevertheless, to be still not
       wholly complete, but to pass into its antithesis, with which it must
       be combined in a new synthesis. In this way Hegel advances until he
       reaches the 'Absolute Idea', which, according to him, has no
       incompleteness, no opposite, and no need of further development. The
       Absolute Idea, therefore, is adequate to describe Absolute Reality;
       but all lower ideas only describe reality as it appears to a partial
       view, not as it is to one who simultaneously surveys the Whole. Thus
       Hegel reaches the conclusion that Absolute Reality forms one single
       harmonious system, not in space or time, not in any degree evil,
       wholly rational, and wholly spiritual. Any appearance to the
       contrary, in the world we know, can be proved logically--so he
       believes--to be entirely due to our fragmentary piecemeal view of the
       universe. If we saw the universe whole, as we may suppose God sees
       it, space and time and matter and evil and all striving and struggling
       would disappear, and we should see instead an eternal perfect
       unchanging spiritual unity.
       In this conception, there is undeniably something sublime, something
       to which we could wish to yield assent. Nevertheless, when the
       arguments in support of it are carefully examined, they appear to
       involve much confusion and many unwarrantable assumptions. The
       fundamental tenet upon which the system is built up is that what is
       incomplete must be not self-subsistent, but must need the support of
       other things before it can exist. It is held that whatever has
       relations to things outside itself must contain some reference to
       those outside things in its own nature, and could not, therefore, be
       what it is if those outside things did not exist. A man's nature, for
       example, is constituted by his memories and the rest of his knowledge,
       by his loves and hatreds, and so on; thus, but for the objects which
       he knows or loves or hates, he could not be what he is. He is
       essentially and obviously a fragment: taken as the sum-total of
       reality he would be self-contradictory.
       This whole point of view, however, turns upon the notion of the
       'nature' of a thing, which seems to mean 'all the truths about the
       thing'. It is of course the case that a truth which connects one
       thing with another thing could not subsist if the other thing did not
       subsist. But a truth about a thing is not part of the thing itself,
       although it must, according to the above usage, be part of the
       'nature' of the thing. If we mean by a thing's 'nature' all the
       truths about the thing, then plainly we cannot know a thing's 'nature'
       unless we know all the thing's relations to all the other things in
       the universe. But if the word 'nature' is used in this sense, we
       shall have to hold that the thing may be known when its 'nature' is
       not known, or at any rate is not known completely. There is a
       confusion, when this use of the word 'nature' is employed, between
       knowledge of things and knowledge of truths. We may have knowledge of
       a thing by acquaintance even if we know very few propositions about
       it--theoretically we need not know any propositions about it. Thus,
       acquaintance with a thing does not involve knowledge of its 'nature'
       in the above sense. And although acquaintance with a thing is
       involved in our knowing any one proposition about a thing, knowledge
       of its 'nature', in the above sense, is not involved. Hence, (1)
       acquaintance with a thing does not logically involve a knowledge of
       its relations, and (2) a knowledge of some of its relations does not
       involve a knowledge of all of its relations nor a knowledge of its
       'nature' in the above sense. I may be acquainted, for example, with
       my toothache, and this knowledge may be as complete as knowledge by
       acquaintance ever can be, without knowing all that the dentist (who is
       not acquainted with it) can tell me about its cause, and without
       therefore knowing its 'nature' in the above sense. Thus the fact that
       a thing has relations does not prove that its relations are logically
       necessary. That is to say, from the mere fact that it is the thing it
       is we cannot deduce that it must have the various relations which in
       fact it has. This only _seems_ to follow because we know it already.
       It follows that we cannot prove that the universe as a whole forms a
       single harmonious system such as Hegel believes that it forms. And if
       we cannot prove this, we also cannot prove the unreality of space and
       time and matter and evil, for this is deduced by Hegel from the
       fragmentary and relational character of these things. Thus we are
       left to the piecemeal investigation of the world, and are unable to
       know the characters of those parts of the universe that are remote
       from our experience. This result, disappointing as it is to those
       whose hopes have been raised by the systems of philosophers, is in
       harmony with the inductive and scientific temper of our age, and is
       borne out by the whole examination of human knowledge which has
       occupied our previous chapters.
       Most of the great ambitious attempts of metaphysicians have proceeded
       by the attempt to prove that such and such apparent features of the
       actual world were self-contradictory, and therefore could not be real.
       The whole tendency of modern thought, however, is more and more in the
       direction of showing that the supposed contradictions were illusory,
       and that very little can be proved _a priori_ from considerations of
       what _must_ be. A good illustration of this is afforded by space and
       time. Space and time appear to be infinite in extent, and infinitely
       divisible. If we travel along a straight line in either direction, it
       is difficult to believe that we shall finally reach a last point,
       beyond which there is nothing, not even empty space. Similarly, if in
       imagination we travel backwards or forwards in time, it is difficult
       to believe that we shall reach a first or last time, with not even
       empty time beyond it. Thus space and time appear to be infinite in
       extent.
       Again, if we take any two points on a line, it seems evident that
       there must be other points between them however small the distance
       between them may be: every distance can be halved, and the halves can
       be halved again, and so on _ad infinitum_. In time, similarly,
       however little time may elapse between two moments, it seems evident
       that there will be other moments between them. Thus space and time
       appear to be infinitely divisible. But as against these apparent
       facts--infinite extent and infinite divisibility--philosophers have
       advanced arguments tending to show that there could be no infinite
       collections of things, and that therefore the number of points in
       space, or of instants in time, must be finite. Thus a contradiction
       emerged between the apparent nature of space and time and the supposed
       impossibility of infinite collections.
       Kant, who first emphasized this contradiction, deduced the
       impossibility of space and time, which he declared to be merely
       subjective; and since his time very many philosophers have believed
       that space and time are mere appearance, not characteristic of the
       world as it really is. Now, however, owing to the labours of the
       mathematicians, notably Georg Cantor, it has appeared that the
       impossibility of infinite collections was a mistake. They are not in
       fact self-contradictory, but only contradictory of certain rather
       obstinate mental prejudices. Hence the reasons for regarding space
       and time as unreal have become inoperative, and one of the great
       sources of metaphysical constructions is dried up.
       The mathematicians, however, have not been content with showing that
       space as it is commonly supposed to be is possible; they have shown
       also that many other forms of space are equally possible, so far as
       logic can show. Some of Euclid's axioms, which appear to common sense
       to be necessary, and were formerly supposed to be necessary by
       philosophers, are now known to derive their appearance of necessity
       from our mere familiarity with actual space, and not from any _a
       priori_ logical foundation. By imagining worlds in which these axioms
       are false, the mathematicians have used logic to loosen the prejudices
       of common sense, and to show the possibility of spaces differing--some
       more, some less--from that in which we live. And some of these spaces
       differ so little from Euclidean space, where distances such as we can
       measure are concerned, that it is impossible to discover by
       observation whether our actual space is strictly Euclidean or of one
       of these other kinds. Thus the position is completely reversed.
       Formerly it appeared that experience left only one kind of space to
       logic, and logic showed this one kind to be impossible. Now, logic
       presents many kinds of space as possible apart from experience, and
       experience only partially decides between them. Thus, while our
       knowledge of what is has become less than it was formerly supposed to
       be, our knowledge of what may be is enormously increased. Instead of
       being shut in within narrow walls, of which every nook and cranny
       could be explored, we find ourselves in an open world of free
       possibilities, where much remains unknown because there is so much to
       know.
       What has happened in the case of space and time has happened, to some
       extent, in other directions as well. The attempt to prescribe to the
       universe by means of _a priori_ principles has broken down; logic,
       instead of being, as formerly, the bar to possibilities, has become
       the great liberator of the imagination, presenting innumerable
       alternatives which are closed to unreflective common sense, and
       leaving to experience the task of deciding, where decision is
       possible, between the many worlds which logic offers for our choice.
       Thus knowledge as to what exists becomes limited to what we can learn
       from experience--not to what we can actually experience, for, as we
       have seen, there is much knowledge by description concerning things of
       which we have no direct experience. But in all cases of knowledge by
       description, we need some connexion of universals, enabling us, from
       such and such a datum, to infer an object of a certain sort as implied
       by our datum. Thus in regard to physical objects, for example, the
       principle that sense-data are signs of physical objects is itself a
       connexion of universals; and it is only in virtue of this principle
       that experience enables us to acquire knowledge concerning physical
       objects. The same applies to the law of causality, or, to descend to
       what is less general, to such principles as the law of gravitation.
       Principles such as the law of gravitation are proved, or rather are
       rendered highly probable, by a combination of experience with some
       wholly _a priori_ principle, such as the principle of induction. Thus
       our intuitive knowledge, which is the source of all our other
       knowledge of truths, is of two sorts: pure empirical knowledge, which
       tells us of the existence and some of the properties of particular
       things with which we are acquainted, and pure _a priori_ knowledge,
       which gives us connexions between universals, and enables us to draw
       inferences from the particular facts given in empirical knowledge.
       Our derivative knowledge always depends upon some pure _a priori_
       knowledge and usually also depends upon some pure empirical knowledge.
       Philosophical knowledge, if what has been said above is true, does not
       differ essentially from scientific knowledge; there is no special
       source of wisdom which is open to philosophy but not to science, and
       the results obtained by philosophy are not radically different from
       those obtained from science. The essential characteristic of
       philosophy, which makes it a study distinct from science, is
       criticism. It examines critically the principles employed in science
       and in daily life; it searches out any inconsistencies there may be in
       these principles, and it only accepts them when, as the result of a
       critical inquiry, no reason for rejecting them has appeared. If, as
       many philosophers have believed, the principles underlying the
       sciences were capable, when disengaged from irrelevant detail, of
       giving us knowledge concerning the universe as a whole, such knowledge
       would have the same claim on our belief as scientific knowledge has;
       but our inquiry has not revealed any such knowledge, and therefore, as
       regards the special doctrines of the bolder metaphysicians, has had a
       mainly negative result. But as regards what would be commonly
       accepted as knowledge, our result is in the main positive: we have
       seldom found reason to reject such knowledge as the result of our
       criticism, and we have seen no reason to suppose man incapable of the
       kind of knowledge which he is generally believed to possess.
       When, however, we speak of philosophy as a _criticism_ of knowledge,
       it is necessary to impose a certain limitation. If we adopt the
       attitude of the complete sceptic, placing ourselves wholly outside all
       knowledge, and asking, from this outside position, to be compelled to
       return within the circle of knowledge, we are demanding what is
       impossible, and our scepticism can never be refuted. For all
       refutation must begin with some piece of knowledge which the
       disputants share; from blank doubt, no argument can begin. Hence the
       criticism of knowledge which philosophy employs must not be of this
       destructive kind, if any result is to be achieved. Against this
       absolute scepticism, no _logical_ argument can be advanced. But it is
       not difficult to see that scepticism of this kind is unreasonable.
       Descartes' 'methodical doubt', with which modern philosophy began, is
       not of this kind, but is rather the kind of criticism which we are
       asserting to be the essence of philosophy. His 'methodical doubt'
       consisted in doubting whatever seemed doubtful; in pausing, with each
       apparent piece of knowledge, to ask himself whether, on reflection, he
       could feel certain that he really knew it. This is the kind of
       criticism which constitutes philosophy. Some knowledge, such as
       knowledge of the existence of our sense-data, appears quite
       indubitable, however calmly and thoroughly we reflect upon it. In
       regard to such knowledge, philosophical criticism does not require
       that we should abstain from belief. But there are beliefs--such, for
       example, as the belief that physical objects exactly resemble our
       sense-data--which are entertained until we begin to reflect, but are
       found to melt away when subjected to a close inquiry. Such beliefs
       philosophy will bid us reject, unless some new line of argument is
       found to support them. But to reject the beliefs which do not appear
       open to any objections, however closely we examine them, is not
       reasonable, and is not what philosophy advocates.
       The criticism aimed at, in a word, is not that which, without reason,
       determines to reject, but that which considers each piece of apparent
       knowledge on its merits, and retains whatever still appears to be
       knowledge when this consideration is completed. That some risk of
       error remains must be admitted, since human beings are fallible.
       Philosophy may claim justly that it diminishes the risk of error, and
       that in some cases it renders the risk so small as to be practically
       negligible. To do more than this is not possible in a world where
       mistakes must occur; and more than this no prudent advocate of
       philosophy would claim to have performed.
       ___
       End of CHAPTER XIV - THE LIMITS OF PHILOSOPHICAL KNOWLEDGE
       [Bertrand Russell's essay: The Problems of Philosophy] _