您的位置 : 首页 > 英文著作
Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER II - THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER
Bertrand Russell
下载:Problems of Philosophy.txt
本书全文检索:
       _ CHAPTER II - THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER
       In this chapter we have to ask ourselves whether, in any sense at all,
       there is such a thing as matter. Is there a table which has a certain
       intrinsic nature, and continues to exist when I am not looking, or is
       the table merely a product of my imagination, a dream-table in a very
       prolonged dream? This question is of the greatest importance. For if
       we cannot be sure of the independent existence of objects, we cannot
       be sure of the independent existence of other people's bodies, and
       therefore still less of other people's minds, since we have no grounds
       for believing in their minds except such as are derived from observing
       their bodies. Thus if we cannot be sure of the independent existence
       of objects, we shall be left alone in a desert--it may be that the
       whole outer world is nothing but a dream, and that we alone exist.
       This is an uncomfortable possibility; but although it cannot be
       strictly proved to be false, there is not the slightest reason to
       suppose that it is true. In this chapter we have to see why this is
       the case.
       Before we embark upon doubtful matters, let us try to find some more
       or less fixed point from which to start. Although we are doubting the
       physical existence of the table, we are not doubting the existence of
       the sense-data which made us think there was a table; we are not
       doubting that, while we look, a certain colour and shape appear to us,
       and while we press, a certain sensation of hardness is experienced by
       us. All this, which is psychological, we are not calling in question.
       In fact, whatever else may be doubtful, some at least of our immediate
       experiences seem absolutely certain.
       Descartes (1596-1650), the founder of modern philosophy, invented a
       method which may still be used with profit--the method of systematic
       doubt. He determined that he would believe nothing which he did not
       see quite clearly and distinctly to be true. Whatever he could bring
       himself to doubt, he would doubt, until he saw reason for not doubting
       it. By applying this method he gradually became convinced that the
       only existence of which he could be _quite_ certain was his own. He
       imagined a deceitful demon, who presented unreal things to his senses
       in a perpetual phantasmagoria; it might be very improbable that such a
       demon existed, but still it was possible, and therefore doubt
       concerning things perceived by the senses was possible.
       But doubt concerning his own existence was not possible, for if he did
       not exist, no demon could deceive him. If he doubted, he must exist;
       if he had any experiences whatever, he must exist. Thus his own
       existence was an absolute certainty to him. 'I think, therefore I
       am,' he said (_Cogito, ergo sum_); and on the basis of this certainty
       he set to work to build up again the world of knowledge which his
       doubt had laid in ruins. By inventing the method of doubt, and by
       showing that subjective things are the most certain, Descartes
       performed a great service to philosophy, and one which makes him still
       useful to all students of the subject.
       But some care is needed in using Descartes' argument. 'I think,
       therefore I am' says rather more than is strictly certain. It might
       seem as though we were quite sure of being the same person to-day as
       we were yesterday, and this is no doubt true in some sense. But the
       real Self is as hard to arrive at as the real table, and does not seem
       to have that absolute, convincing certainty that belongs to particular
       experiences. When I look at my table and see a certain brown colour,
       what is quite certain at once is not '_I_ am seeing a brown colour',
       but rather, 'a brown colour is being seen'. This of course involves
       something (or somebody) which (or who) sees the brown colour; but it
       does not of itself involve that more or less permanent person whom we
       call ' I'. So far as immediate certainty goes, it might be that the
       something which sees the brown colour is quite momentary, and not the
       same as the something which has some different experience the next
       moment.
       Thus it is our particular thoughts and feelings that have primitive
       certainty. And this applies to dreams and hallucinations as well as
       to normal perceptions: when we dream or see a ghost, we certainly do
       have the sensations we think we have, but for various reasons it is
       held that no physical object corresponds to these sensations. Thus
       the certainty of our knowledge of our own experiences does not have to
       be limited in any way to allow for exceptional cases. Here,
       therefore, we have, for what it is worth, a solid basis from which to
       begin our pursuit of knowledge.
       The problem we have to consider is this: Granted that we are certain
       of our own sense-data, have we any reason for regarding them as signs
       of the existence of something else, which we can call the physical
       object? When we have enumerated all the sense-data which we should
       naturally regard as connected with the table, have we said all there
       is to say about the table, or is there still something else--something
       not a sense-datum, something which persists when we go out of the
       room? Common sense unhesitatingly answers that there is. What can be
       bought and sold and pushed about and have a cloth laid on it, and so
       on, cannot be a _mere_ collection of sense-data. If the cloth
       completely hides the table, we shall derive no sense-data from the
       table, and therefore, if the table were merely sense-data, it would
       have ceased to exist, and the cloth would be suspended in empty air,
       resting, by a miracle, in the place where the table formerly was.
       This seems plainly absurd; but whoever wishes to become a philosopher
       must learn not to be frightened by absurdities.
       One great reason why it is felt that we must secure a physical object
       in addition to the sense-data, is that we want the same object for
       different people. When ten people are sitting round a dinner-table,
       it seems preposterous to maintain that they are not seeing the same
       tablecloth, the same knives and forks and spoons and glasses. But the
       sense-data are private to each separate person; what is immediately
       present to the sight of one is not immediately present to the sight of
       another: they all see things from slightly different points of view,
       and therefore see them slightly differently. Thus, if there are to be
       public neutral objects, which can be in some sense known to many
       different people, there must be something over and above the private
       and particular sense-data which appear to various people. What
       reason, then, have we for believing that there are such public neutral
       objects?
       The first answer that naturally occurs to one is that, although
       different people may see the table slightly differently, still they
       all see more or less similar things when they look at the table, and
       the variations in what they see follow the laws of perspective and
       reflection of light, so that it is easy to arrive at a permanent
       object underlying all the different people's sense-data. I bought my
       table from the former occupant of my room; I could not buy _his_
       sense-data, which died when he went away, but I could and did buy the
       confident expectation of more or less similar sense-data. Thus it is
       the fact that different people have similar sense-data, and that one
       person in a given place at different times has similar sense-data,
       which makes us suppose that over and above the sense-data there is a
       permanent public object which underlies or causes the sense-data of
       various people at various times.
       Now in so far as the above considerations depend upon supposing that
       there are other people besides ourselves, they beg the very question
       at issue. Other people are represented to me by certain sense-data,
       such as the sight of them or the sound of their voices, and if I had
       no reason to believe that there were physical objects independent of
       my sense-data, I should have no reason to believe that other people
       exist except as part of my dream. Thus, when we are trying to show
       that there must be objects independent of our own sense-data, we
       cannot appeal to the testimony of other people, since this testimony
       itself consists of sense-data, and does not reveal other people's
       experiences unless our own sense-data are signs of things existing
       independently of us. We must therefore, if possible, find, in our own
       purely private experiences, characteristics which show, or tend to
       show, that there are in the world things other than ourselves and our
       private experiences.
       In one sense it must be admitted that we can never prove the existence
       of things other than ourselves and our experiences. No logical
       absurdity results from the hypothesis that the world consists of
       myself and my thoughts and feelings and sensations, and that
       everything else is mere fancy. In dreams a very complicated world may
       seem to be present, and yet on waking we find it was a delusion; that
       is to say, we find that the sense-data in the dream do not appear to
       have corresponded with such physical objects as we should naturally
       infer from our sense-data. (It is true that, when the physical world
       is assumed, it is possible to find physical causes for the sense-data
       in dreams: a door banging, for instance, may cause us to dream of a
       naval engagement. But although, in this case, there is a physical
       cause for the sense-data, there is not a physical object corresponding
       to the sense-data in the way in which an actual naval battle would
       correspond.) There is no logical impossibility in the supposition that
       the whole of life is a dream, in which we ourselves create all the
       objects that come before us. But although this is not logically
       impossible, there is no reason whatever to suppose that it is true;
       and it is, in fact, a less simple hypothesis, viewed as a means of
       accounting for the facts of our own life, than the common-sense
       hypothesis that there really are objects independent of us, whose
       action on us causes our sensations.
       The way in which simplicity comes in from supposing that there really
       are physical objects is easily seen. If the cat appears at one moment
       in one part of the room, and at another in another part, it is natural
       to suppose that it has moved from the one to the other, passing over a
       series of intermediate positions. But if it is merely a set of
       sense-data, it cannot have ever been in any place where I did not see
       it; thus we shall have to suppose that it did not exist at all while I
       was not looking, but suddenly sprang into being in a new place. If
       the cat exists whether I see it or not, we can understand from our own
       experience how it gets hungry between one meal and the next; but if it
       does not exist when I am not seeing it, it seems odd that appetite
       should grow during non-existence as fast as during existence. And if
       the cat consists only of sense-data, it cannot be hungry, since no
       hunger but my own can be a sense-datum to me. Thus the behaviour of
       the sense-data which represent the cat to me, though it seems quite
       natural when regarded as an expression of hunger, becomes utterly
       inexplicable when regarded as mere movements and changes of patches of
       colour, which are as incapable of hunger as a triangle is of playing
       football.
       But the difficulty in the case of the cat is nothing compared to the
       difficulty in the case of human beings. When human beings speak--that
       is, when we hear certain noises which we associate with ideas, and
       simultaneously see certain motions of lips and expressions of face--it
       is very difficult to suppose that what we hear is not the expression
       of a thought, as we know it would be if we emitted the same sounds.
       Of course similar things happen in dreams, where we are mistaken as to
       the existence of other people. But dreams are more or less suggested
       by what we call waking life, and are capable of being more or less
       accounted for on scientific principles if we assume that there really
       is a physical world. Thus every principle of simplicity urges us to
       adopt the natural view, that there really are objects other than
       ourselves and our sense-data which have an existence not dependent
       upon our perceiving them.
       Of course it is not by argument that we originally come by our belief
       in an independent external world. We find this belief ready in
       ourselves as soon as we begin to reflect: it is what may be called an
       _instinctive_ belief. We should never have been led to question this
       belief but for the fact that, at any rate in the case of sight, it
       seems as if the sense-datum itself were instinctively believed to be
       the independent object, whereas argument shows that the object cannot
       be identical with the sense-datum. This discovery, however--which is
       not at all paradoxical in the case of taste and smell and sound, and
       only slightly so in the case of touch--leaves undiminished our
       instinctive belief that there _are_ objects _corresponding_ to our
       sense-data. Since this belief does not lead to any difficulties, but
       on the contrary tends to simplify and systematize our account of our
       experiences, there seems no good reason for rejecting it. We may
       therefore admit--though with a slight doubt derived from dreams--that
       the external world does really exist, and is not wholly dependent for
       its existence upon our continuing to perceive it.
       The argument which has led us to this conclusion is doubtless less
       strong than we could wish, but it is typical of many philosophical
       arguments, and it is therefore worth while to consider briefly its
       general character and validity. All knowledge, we find, must be built
       up upon our instinctive beliefs, and if these are rejected, nothing is
       left. But among our instinctive beliefs some are much stronger than
       others, while many have, by habit and association, become entangled
       with other beliefs, not really instinctive, but falsely supposed to be
       part of what is believed instinctively.
       Philosophy should show us the hierarchy of our instinctive beliefs,
       beginning with those we hold most strongly, and presenting each as
       much isolated and as free from irrelevant additions as possible. It
       should take care to show that, in the form in which they are finally
       set forth, our instinctive beliefs do not clash, but form a harmonious
       system. There can never be any reason for rejecting one instinctive
       belief except that it clashes with others; thus, if they are found to
       harmonize, the whole system becomes worthy of acceptance.
       It is of course _possible_ that all or any of our beliefs may be
       mistaken, and therefore all ought to be held with at least some slight
       element of doubt. But we cannot have _reason_ to reject a belief
       except on the ground of some other belief. Hence, by organizing our
       instinctive beliefs and their consequences, by considering which among
       them is most possible, if necessary, to modify or abandon, we can
       arrive, on the basis of accepting as our sole data what we
       instinctively believe, at an orderly systematic organization of our
       knowledge, in which, though the _possibility_ of error remains, its
       likelihood is diminished by the interrelation of the parts and by the
       critical scrutiny which has preceded acquiescence.
       This function, at least, philosophy can perform. Most philosophers,
       rightly or wrongly, believe that philosophy can do much more than
       this--that it can give us knowledge, not otherwise attainable,
       concerning the universe as a whole, and concerning the nature of
       ultimate reality. Whether this be the case or not, the more modest
       function we have spoken of can certainly be performed by philosophy,
       and certainly suffices, for those who have once begun to doubt the
       adequacy of common sense, to justify the arduous and difficult labours
       that philosophical problems involve.
        
       ___
       End of CHAPTER II - THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER[Bertrand Russell's essay: Problems of Philosophy] _