您的位置 : 首页 > 英文著作
Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER X - ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF UNIVERSALS
Bertrand Russell
下载:Problems of Philosophy.txt
本书全文检索:
       _ CHAPTER X - ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF UNIVERSALS
       In regard to one man's knowledge at a given time, universals, like
       particulars, may be divided into those known by acquaintance, those
       known only by description, and those not known either by acquaintance
       or by description.
       Let us consider first the knowledge of universals by acquaintance. It
       is obvious, to begin with, that we are acquainted with such universals
       as white, red, black, sweet, sour, loud, hard, etc., i.e. with
       qualities which are exemplified in sense-data. When we see a white
       patch, we are acquainted, in the first instance, with the particular
       patch; but by seeing many white patches, we easily learn to abstract
       the whiteness which they all have in common, and in learning to do
       this we are learning to be acquainted with whiteness. A similar
       process will make us acquainted with any other universal of the same
       sort. Universals of this sort may be called 'sensible qualities'.
       They can be apprehended with less effort of abstraction than any
       others, and they seem less removed from particulars than other
       universals are.
       We come next to relations. The easiest relations to apprehend are
       those which hold between the different parts of a single complex
       sense-datum. For example, I can see at a glance the whole of the page
       on which I am writing; thus the whole page is included in one
       sense-datum. But I perceive that some parts of the page are to the
       left of other parts, and some parts are above other parts. The
       process of abstraction in this case seems to proceed somewhat as
       follows: I see successively a number of sense-data in which one part
       is to the left of another; I perceive, as in the case of different
       white patches, that all these sense-data have something in common, and
       by abstraction I find that what they have in common is a certain
       relation between their parts, namely the relation which I call 'being
       to the left of'. In this way I become acquainted with the universal
       relation.
       In like manner I become aware of the relation of before and after in
       time. Suppose I hear a chime of bells: when the last bell of the
       chime sounds, I can retain the whole chime before my mind, and I can
       perceive that the earlier bells came before the later ones. Also in
       memory I perceive that what I am remembering came before the present
       time. From either of these sources I can abstract the universal
       relation of before and after, just as I abstracted the universal
       relation 'being to the left of'. Thus time-relations, like
       space-relations, are among those with which we are acquainted.
       Another relation with which we become acquainted in much the same way
       is resemblance. If I see simultaneously two shades of green, I can
       see that they resemble each other; if I also see a shade of red: at
       the same time, I can see that the two greens have more resemblance to
       each other than either has to the red. In this way I become
       acquainted with the universal _resemblance_ or _similarity_.
       Between universals, as between particulars, there are relations of
       which we may be immediately aware. We have just seen that we can
       perceive that the resemblance between two shades of green is greater
       than the resemblance between a shade of red and a shade of green.
       Here we are dealing with a relation, namely 'greater than', between
       two relations. Our knowledge of such relations, though it requires
       more power of abstraction than is required for perceiving the
       qualities of sense-data, appears to be equally immediate, and (at
       least in some cases) equally indubitable. Thus there is immediate
       knowledge concerning universals as well as concerning sense-data.
       Returning now to the problem of _a priori_ knowledge, which we left
       unsolved when we began the consideration of universals, we find
       ourselves in a position to deal with it in a much more satisfactory
       manner than was possible before. Let us revert to the proposition
       'two and two are four'. It is fairly obvious, in view of what has
       been said, that this proposition states a relation between the
       universal 'two' and the universal 'four'. This suggests a proposition
       which we shall now endeavour to establish: namely, _All _a priori_
       knowledge deals exclusively with the relations of universals_. This
       proposition is of great importance, and goes a long way towards
       solving our previous difficulties concerning _a priori_ knowledge.
       The only case in which it might seem, at first sight, as if our
       proposition were untrue, is the case in which an _a priori_
       proposition states that _all_ of one class of particulars belong to
       some other class, or (what comes to the same thing) that _all_
       particulars having some one property also have some other. In this
       case it might seem as though we were dealing with the particulars that
       have the property rather than with the property. The proposition 'two
       and two are four' is really a case in point, for this may be stated in
       the form 'any two and any other two are four', or 'any collection
       formed of two twos is a collection of four'. If we can show that such
       statements as this really deal only with universals, our proposition
       may be regarded as proved.
       One way of discovering what a proposition deals with is to ask
       ourselves what words we must understand--in other words, what objects
       we must be acquainted with--in order to see what the proposition
       means. As soon as we see what the proposition means, even if we do
       not yet know whether it is true or false, it is evident that we must
       have acquaintance with whatever is really dealt with by the
       proposition. By applying this test, it appears that many propositions
       which might seem to be concerned with particulars are really concerned
       only with universals. In the special case of 'two and two are four',
       even when we interpret it as meaning 'any collection formed of two
       twos is a collection of four', it is plain that we can understand the
       proposition, i.e. we can see what it is that it asserts, as soon as
       we know what is meant by 'collection' and 'two' and 'four'. It is
       quite unnecessary to know all the couples in the world: if it were
       necessary, obviously we could never understand the proposition, since
       the couples are infinitely numerous and therefore cannot all be known
       to us. Thus although our general statement _implies_ statements about
       particular couples, _as soon as we know that there are such particular
       couples_, yet it does not itself assert or imply that there are such
       particular couples, and thus fails to make any statement whatever
       about any actual particular couple. The statement made is about
       'couple', the universal, and not about this or that couple.
       Thus the statement 'two and two are four' deals exclusively with
       universals, and therefore may be known by anybody who is acquainted
       with the universals concerned and can perceive the relation between
       them which the statement asserts. It must be taken as a fact,
       discovered by reflecting upon our knowledge, that we have the power of
       sometimes perceiving such relations between universals, and therefore
       of sometimes knowing general _a priori_ propositions such as those of
       arithmetic and logic. The thing that seemed mysterious, when we
       formerly considered such knowledge, was that it seemed to anticipate
       and control experience. This, however, we can now see to have been an
       error. _No_ fact concerning anything capable of being experienced can
       be known independently of experience. We know _a priori_ that two
       things and two other things together make four things, but we do _not_
       know _a priori_ that if Brown and Jones are two, and Robinson and
       Smith are two, then Brown and Jones and Robinson and Smith are four.
       The reason is that this proposition cannot be understood at all unless
       we know that there are such people as Brown and Jones and Robinson and
       Smith, and this we can only know by experience. Hence, although our
       general proposition is _a priori_, all its applications to actual
       particulars involve experience and therefore contain an empirical
       element. In this way what seemed mysterious in our _a priori_
       knowledge is seen to have been based upon an error.
       It will serve to make the point clearer if we contrast our genuine _a
       priori_ judgement with an empirical generalization, such as 'all men
       are mortals'. Here as before, we can _understand_ what the
       proposition means as soon as we understand the universals involved,
       namely _man_ and _mortal_. It is obviously unnecessary to have an
       individual acquaintance with the whole human race in order to
       understand what our proposition means. Thus the difference between an
       _a priori_ general proposition and an empirical generalization does
       not come in the _meaning_ of the proposition; it comes in the nature
       of the _evidence_ for it. In the empirical case, the evidence
       consists in the particular instances. We believe that all men are
       mortal because we know that there are innumerable instances of men
       dying, and no instances of their living beyond a certain age. We do
       not believe it because we see a connexion between the universal _man_
       and the universal _mortal_. It is true that if physiology can prove,
       assuming the general laws that govern living bodies, that no living
       organism can last for ever, that gives a connexion between _man_ and
       _mortality_ which would enable us to assert our proposition without
       appealing to the special evidence of _men_ dying. But that only means
       that our generalization has been subsumed under a wider
       generalization, for which the evidence is still of the same kind,
       though more extensive. The progress of science is constantly
       producing such subsumptions, and therefore giving a constantly wider
       inductive basis for scientific generalizations. But although this
       gives a greater _degree_ of certainty, it does not give a different
       _kind_: the ultimate ground remains inductive, i.e. derived from
       instances, and not an _a priori_ connexion of universals such as we
       have in logic and arithmetic.
       Two opposite points are to be observed concerning _a priori_ general
       propositions. The first is that, if many particular instances are
       known, our general proposition may be arrived at in the first instance
       by induction, and the connexion of universals may be only subsequently
       perceived. For example, it is known that if we draw perpendiculars to
       the sides of a triangle from the opposite angles, all three
       perpendiculars meet in a point. It would be quite possible to be
       first led to this proposition by actually drawing perpendiculars in
       many cases, and finding that they always met in a point; this
       experience might lead us to look for the general proof and find it.
       Such cases are common in the experience of every mathematician.
       The other point is more interesting, and of more philosophical
       importance. It is, that we may sometimes know a general proposition
       in cases where we do not know a single instance of it. Take such a
       case as the following: We know that any two numbers can be multiplied
       together, and will give a third called their _product_. We know that
       all pairs of integers the product of which is less than 100 have been
       actually multiplied together, and the value of the product recorded in
       the multiplication table. But we also know that the number of
       integers is infinite, and that only a finite number of pairs of
       integers ever have been or ever will be thought of by human beings.
       Hence it follows that there are pairs of integers which never have
       been and never will be thought of by human beings, and that all of
       them deal with integers the product of which is over 100. Hence we
       arrive at the proposition: 'All products of two integers, which never
       have been and never will be thought of by any human being, are over
       100.' Here is a general proposition of which the truth is undeniable,
       and yet, from the very nature of the case, we can never give an
       instance; because any two numbers we may think of are excluded by the
       terms of the proposition.
       This possibility, of knowledge of general propositions of which no
       instance can be given, is often denied, because it is not perceived
       that the knowledge of such propositions only requires a knowledge of
       the relations of universals, and does not require any knowledge of
       instances of the universals in question. Yet the knowledge of such
       general propositions is quite vital to a great deal of what is
       generally admitted to be known. For example, we saw, in our early
       chapters, that knowledge of physical objects, as opposed to
       sense-data, is only obtained by an inference, and that they are not
       things with which we are acquainted. Hence we can never know any
       proposition of the form 'this is a physical object', where 'this' is
       something immediately known. It follows that all our knowledge
       concerning physical objects is such that no actual instance can be
       given. We can give instances of the associated sense-data, but we
       cannot give instances of the actual physical objects. Hence our
       knowledge as to physical objects depends throughout upon this
       possibility of general knowledge where no instance can be given. And
       the same applies to our knowledge of other people's minds, or of any
       other class of things of which no instance is known to us by
       acquaintance.
       We may now take a survey of the sources of our knowledge, as they have
       appeared in the course of our analysis. We have first to distinguish
       knowledge of things and knowledge of truths. In each there are two
       kinds, one immediate and one derivative. Our immediate knowledge of
       things, which we called _acquaintance_, consists of two sorts,
       according as the things known are particulars or universals. Among
       particulars, we have acquaintance with sense-data and (probably) with
       ourselves. Among universals, there seems to be no principle by which
       we can decide which can be known by acquaintance, but it is clear that
       among those that can be so known are sensible qualities, relations of
       space and time, similarity, and certain abstract logical universals.
       Our derivative knowledge of things, which we call knowledge by
       _description_, always involves both acquaintance with something and
       knowledge of truths. Our immediate knowledge of _truths_ may be
       called _intuitive_ knowledge, and the truths so known may be called
       _self-evident_ truths. Among such truths are included those which
       merely state what is given in sense, and also certain abstract logical
       and arithmetical principles, and (though with less certainty) some
       ethical propositions. Our _derivative_ knowledge of truths consists
       of everything that we can deduce from self-evident truths by the use
       of self-evident principles of deduction.
       If the above account is correct, all our knowledge of truths depends
       upon our intuitive knowledge. It therefore becomes important to
       consider the nature and scope of intuitive knowledge, in much the same
       way as, at an earlier stage, we considered the nature and scope of
       knowledge by acquaintance. But knowledge of truths raises a further
       problem, which does not arise in regard to knowledge of things, namely
       the problem of _error_. Some of our beliefs turn out to be erroneous,
       and therefore it becomes necessary to consider how, if at all, we can
       distinguish knowledge from error. This problem does not arise with
       regard to knowledge by acquaintance, for, whatever may be the object
       of acquaintance, even in dreams and hallucinations, there is no error
       involved so long as we do not go beyond the immediate object: error
       can only arise when we regard the immediate object, i.e. the
       sense-datum, as the mark of some physical object. Thus the problems
       connected with knowledge of truths are more difficult than those
       connected with knowledge of things. As the first of the problems
       connected with knowledge of truths, let us examine the nature and
       scope of our intuitive judgements.
        
       ___
       End of CHAPTER X - ON OUR KNOWLEDGE OF UNIVERSALS
       [Bertrand Russell's essay: The Problems of Philosophy] _