您的位置 : 首页 > 英文著作
Notebooks of Leonardo Da Vinci, The
VOLUME I   VOLUME I - II. LINEAR PERSPECTIVE
Leonardo da Vinci
下载:Notebooks of Leonardo Da Vinci, The.txt
本书全文检索:
       _
       VOLUME I - II. LINEAR PERSPECTIVE
       Linear Perspective
       We see clearly from the concluding sentence of section 49, where the
       author directly addresses the painter, that he must certainly have
       intended to include the elements of mathematics in his Book on the
       art of Painting. They are therefore here placed at the beginning. In
       section 50 the theory of the "Pyramid of Sight" is distinctly and
       expressly put forward as the fundamental principle of linear
       perspective, and sections 52 to 57 treat of it fully. This theory of
       sight can scarcely be traced to any author of antiquity. Such
       passages as occur in Euclid for instance, may, it is true, have
       proved suggestive to the painters of the Renaissance, but it would
       be rash to say any thing decisive on this point.
       Leon Battista Alberti treats of the "Pyramid of Sight" at some
       length in his first Book of Painting; but his explanation differs
       widely from Leonardo's in the details. Leonardo, like Alberti, may
       have borrowed the broad lines of his theory from some views commonly
       accepted among painters at the time; but he certainly worked out its
       application in a perfectly original manner.
       The axioms as to the perception of the pyramid of rays are followed
       by explanations of its origin, and proofs of its universal
       application (58--69). The author recurs to the subject with endless
       variations; it is evidently of fundamental importance in his
       artistic theory and practice. It is unnecessary to discuss how far
       this theory has any scientific value at the present day; so much as
       this, at any rate, seems certain: that from the artist's point of
       view it may still claim to be of immense practical utility.
       According to Leonardo, on one hand, the laws of perspective are an
       inalienable condition of the existence of objects in space; on the
       other hand, by a natural law, the eye, whatever it sees and wherever
       it turns, is subjected to the perception of the pyramid of rays in
       the form of a minute target. Thus it sees objects in perspective
       independently of the will of the spectator, since the eye receives
       the images by means of the pyramid of rays "just as a magnet
       attracts iron".
       In connection with this we have the function of the eye explained by
       the Camera obscura, and this is all the more interesting and
       important because no writer previous to Leonardo had treated of this
       subject_ (70--73). _Subsequent passages, of no less special interest,
       betray his knowledge of refraction and of the inversion of the image
       in the camera and in the eye_ (74--82).
       _From the principle of the transmission of the image to the eye and
       to the camera obscura he deduces the means of producing an
       artificial construction of the pyramid of rays or--which is the same
       thing--of the image. The fundamental axioms as to the angle of sight
       and the vanishing point are thus presented in a manner which is as
       complete as it is simple and intelligible_ (86--89).
       _Leonardo distinguishes between simple and complex perspective_ (90,
       91). _The last sections treat of the apparent size of objects at
       various distances and of the way to estimate it_ (92--109).
       General remarks on perspective (40-41)
       40.
       ON PAINTING.
       Perspective is the best guide to the art of Painting.
       [Footnote: 40. Compare 53, 2.]
       41.
       The art of perspective is of such a nature as to make what is flat
       appear in relief and what is in relief flat.
       The elements of perspective--Of the Point (42-46)
       42.
       All the problems of perspective are made clear by the five terms of
       mathematicians, which are:--the point, the line, the angle, the
       superficies and the solid. The point is unique of its kind. And the
       point has neither height, breadth, length, nor depth, whence it is
       to be regarded as indivisible and as having no dimensions in space.
       The line is of three kinds, straight, curved and sinuous and it has
       neither breadth, height, nor depth. Hence it is indivisible,
       excepting in its length, and its ends are two points. The angle is
       the junction of two lines in a point.
       43.
       A point is not part of a line.
       44.
       OF THE NATURAL POINT.
       The smallest natural point is larger than all mathematical points,
       and this is proved because the natural point has continuity, and any
       thing that is continuous is infinitely divisible; but the
       mathematical point is indivisible because it has no size.
       [Footnote: This definition was inserted by Leonardo on a MS. copy on
       parchment of the well-known _"Trattato d'Architettura civile e
       militare"_ &c. by FRANCESCO DI GIORGIO; opposite a passage where the
       author says: _'In prima he da sapere che punto e quella parie della
       quale he nulla--Linia he luncheza senza apieza; &c.]
       45.
       1, The superficies is a limitation of the body. 2, and the
       limitation of a body is no part of that body. 4, and the limitation
       of one body is that which begins another. 3, that which is not part
       of any body is nothing. Nothing is that which fills no space.
       If one single point placed in a circle may be the starting point of
       an infinite number of lines, and the termination of an infinite
       number of lines, there must be an infinite number of points
       separable from this point, and these when reunited become one again;
       whence it follows that the part may be equal to the whole.
       46.
       The point, being indivisible, occupies no space. That which occupies
       no space is nothing. The limiting surface of one thing is the
       beginning of another. 2. That which is no part of any body is called
       nothing. 1. That which has no limitations, has no form. The
       limitations of two conterminous bodies are interchangeably the
       surface of each. All the surfaces of a body are not parts of that
       body.
       Of the line (47-48)
       47.
       DEFINITION OF THE NATURE OF THE LINE.
       The line has in itself neither matter nor substance and may rather
       be called an imaginary idea than a real object; and this being its
       nature it occupies no space. Therefore an infinite number of lines
       may be conceived of as intersecting each other at a point, which has
       no dimensions and is only of the thickness (if thickness it may be
       called) of one single line.
       HOW WE MAY CONCLUDE THAT A SUPERFICIES TERMINATES IN A POINT?
       An angular surface is reduced to a point where it terminates in an
       angle. Or, if the sides of that angle are produced in a straight
       line, then--beyond that angle--another surface is generated,
       smaller, or equal to, or larger than the first.
       48.
       OF DRAWING OUTLINE.
       Consider with the greatest care the form of the outlines of every
       object, and the character of their undulations. And these
       undulations must be separately studied, as to whether the curves are
       composed of arched convexities or angular concavities.
       The nature of the outline (49)
       49.
       The boundaries of bodies are the least of all things. The
       proposition is proved to be true, because the boundary of a thing is
       a surface, which is not part of the body contained within that
       surface; nor is it part of the air surrounding that body, but is the
       medium interposted between the air and the body, as is proved in its
       place. But the lateral boundaries of these bodies is the line
       forming the boundary of the surface, which line is of invisible
       thickness. Wherefore O painter! do not surround your bodies with
       lines, and above all when representing objects smaller than nature;
       for not only will their external outlines become indistinct, but
       their parts will be invisible from distance.
       Definition of Perspective (50)
       50.
       [Drawing is based upon perspective, which is nothing else than a
       thorough knowledge of the function of the eye. And this function
       simply consists in receiving in a pyramid the forms and colours of
       all the objects placed before it. I say in a pyramid, because there
       is no object so small that it will not be larger than the spot where
       these pyramids are received into the eye. Therefore, if you extend
       the lines from the edges of each body as they converge you will
       bring them to a single point, and necessarily the said lines must
       form a pyramid.]
       [Perspective is nothing more than a rational demonstration applied
       to the consideration of how objects in front of the eye transmit
       their image to it, by means of a pyramid of lines. The _Pyramid_ is
       the name I apply to the lines which, starting from the surface and
       edges of each object, converge from a distance and meet in a single
       point.]
       [Perspective is a rational demonstration, by which we may
       practically and clearly understand how objects transmit their own
       image, by lines forming a Pyramid (centred) in the eye.]
       Perspective is a rational demonstration by which experience confirms
       that every object sends its image to the eye by a pyramid of lines;
       and bodies of equal size will result in a pyramid of larger or
       smaller size, according to the difference in their distance, one
       from the other. By a pyramid of lines I mean those which start from
       the surface and edges of bodies, and, converging from a distance
       meet in a single point. A point is said to be that which [having no
       dimensions] cannot be divided, and this point placed in the eye
       receives all the points of the cone.
       [Footnote: 50. 1-5. Compare with this the Proem. No. 21. The
       paragraphs placed in brackets: lines 1-9, 10-14, and 17--20, are
       evidently mere sketches and, as such, were cancelled by the writer;
       but they serve as a commentary on the final paragraph, lines 22-29.]
       The perception of the object depends on the direction of the eye (51)
       IN WHAT WAY THE EYE SEES OBJECTS PLACED IN FRONT OF IT.
       51.
       Supposing that the ball figured above is the ball of the eye and let
       the small portion of the ball which is cut off by the line _s t_ be
       the pupil and all the objects mirrored on the centre of the face of
       the eye, by means of the pupil, pass on at once and enter the pupil,
       passing through the crystalline humour, which does not interfere in
       the pupil with the things seen by means of the light. And the pupil
       having received the objects, by means of the light, immediately
       refers them and transmits them to the intellect by the line _a b_.
       And you must know that the pupil transmits nothing perfectly to the
       intellect or common sense excepting when the objects presented to it
       by means of light, reach it by the line _a b;_ as, for instance, by
       the line _b c_. For although the lines _m n_ and _f g_ may be seen
       by the pupil they are not perfectly taken in, because they do not
       coincide with the line _a b_. And the proof is this: If the eye,
       shown above, wants to count the letters placed in front, the eye
       will be obliged to turn from letter to letter, because it cannot
       discern them unless they lie in the line _a b;_ as, for instance, in
       the line _a c_. All visible objects reach the eye by the lines of a
       pyramid, and the point of the pyramid is the apex and centre of it,
       in the centre of the pupil, as figured above.
       [Footnote: 51. In this problem the eye is conceived of as fixed and
       immovable; this is plain from line 11.]
       Experimental proof of the existence of the pyramid of sight (52-55)
       52.
       Perspective is a rational demonstration, confirmed by experience,
       that all objects transmit their image to the eye by a pyramid of
       lines.
       By a pyramid of lines I understand those lines which start from the
       edges of the surface of bodies, and converging from a distance, meet
       in a single point; and this point, in the present instance, I will
       show to be situated in the eye which is the universal judge of all
       objects. By a point I mean that which cannot be divided into parts;
       therefore this point, which is situated in the eye, being
       indivisible, no body is seen by the eye, that is not larger than
       this point. This being the case it is inevitable that the lines
       which come from the object to the point must form a pyramid. And if
       any man seeks to prove that the sense of sight does not reside in
       this point, but rather in the black spot which is visible in the
       middle of the pupil, I might reply to him that a small object could
       never diminish at any distance, as it might be a grain of millet or
       of oats or of some similar thing, and that object, if it were larger
       than the said [black] spot would never be seen as a whole; as may be
       seen in the diagram below. Let _a_. be the seat of sight, _b e_ the
       lines which reach the eye. Let _e d_ be the grains of millet within
       these lines. You plainly see that these will never diminish by
       distance, and that the body _m n_ could not be entirely covered by
       it. Therefore you must confess that the eye contains within itself
       one single indivisible point _a_, to which all the points converge
       of the pyramid of lines starting from an object, as is shown below.
       Let _a_. _b_. be the eye; in the centre of it is the point above
       mentioned. If the line _e f_ is to enter as an image into so small
       an opening in the eye, you must confess that the smaller object
       cannot enter into what is smaller than itself unless it is
       diminished, and by diminishing it must take the form of a pyramid.
       53.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       Perspective comes in where judgment fails [as to the distance] in
       objects which diminish. The eye can never be a true judge for
       determining with exactitude how near one object is to another which
       is equal to it [in size], if the top of that other is on the level
       of the eye which sees them on that side, excepting by means of the
       vertical plane which is the standard and guide of perspective. Let
       _n_ be the eye, _e f_ the vertical plane above mentioned. Let _a b c
       d_ be the three divisions, one below the other; if the lines _a n_
       and _c n_ are of a given length and the eye _n_ is in the centre,
       then _a b_ will look as large as _b c. c d_ is lower and farther off
       from _n_, therefore it will look smaller. And the same effect will
       appear in the three divisions of a face when the eye of the painter
       who is drawing it is on a level with the eye of the person he is
       painting.
       54.
       TO PROVE HOW OBJECTS REACH THE EYE.
       If you look at the sun or some other luminous body and then shut
       your eyes you will see it again inside your eye for a long time.
       This is evidence that images enter into the eye.
       The relations of the distance points to the vanishing point (55-56)
       55.
       ELEMENTS OF PERSPECTIVE.
       All objects transmit their image to the eye in pyramids, and the
       nearer to the eye these pyramids are intersected the smaller will
       the image appear of the objects which cause them. Therefore, you may
       intersect the pyramid with a vertical plane [Footnote 4: _Pariete_.
       Compare the definitions in 85, 2-5, 6-27. These lines refer
       exclusively to the third diagram. For the better understanding of
       this it should be observed that _c s_ must be regarded as
       representing the section or profile of a square plane, placed
       horizontally (comp. lines 11, 14, 17) for which the word _pianura_
       is subsequently employed (20, 22). Lines 6-13 contain certain
       preliminary observations to guide the reader in understanding the
       diagram; the last three seem to have been added as a supplement.
       Leonardo's mistake in writing _t denota_ (line 6) for _f denota_ has
       been rectified.] which reaches the base of the pyramid as is shown
       in the plane _a n_.
       The eye _f_ and the eye _t_ are one and the same thing; but the eye
       _f_ marks the distance, that is to say how far you are standing from
       the object; and the eye _t_ shows you the direction of it; that is
       whether you are opposite, or on one side, or at an angle to the
       object you are looking at. And remember that the eye _f_ and the eye
       _t_ must always be kept on the same level. For example if you raise
       or lower the eye from the distance point _f_ you must do the same
       with the direction point _t_. And if the point _f_ shows how far the
       eye is distant from the square plane but does not show on which side
       it is placed--and, if in the same way, the point _t_ show _s_ the
       direction and not the distance, in order to ascertain both you must
       use both points and they will be one and the same thing. If the eye
       _f_ could see a perfect square of which all the sides were equal to
       the distance between _s_ and _c_, and if at the nearest end of the
       side towards the eye a pole were placed, or some other straight
       object, set up by a perpendicular line as shown at _r s_--then, I
       say, that if you were to look at the side of the square that is
       nearest to you it will appear at the bottom of the vertical plane _r
       s_, and then look at the farther side and it would appear to you at
       the height of the point _n_ on the vertical plane. Thus, by this
       example, you can understand that if the eye is above a number of
       objects all placed on the same level, one beyond another, the more
       remote they are the higher they will seem, up to the level of the
       eye, but no higher; because objects placed upon the level on which
       your feet stand, so long as it is flat--even if it be extended into
       infinity--would never be seen above the eye; since the eye has in
       itself the point towards which all the cones tend and converge which
       convey the images of the objects to the eye. And this point always
       coincides with the point of diminution which is the extreme of all
       we can see. And from the base line of the first pyramid as far as
       the diminishing point
       [Footnote: The two diagrams above the chapter are explained by the
       first five lines. They have, however, more letters than are referred
       to in the text, a circumstance we frequently find occasion to
       remark.]
       56.
       there are only bases without pyramids which constantly diminish up
       to this point. And from the first base where the vertical plane is
       placed towards the point in the eye there will be only pyramids
       without bases; as shown in the example given above. Now, let _a b_
       be the said vertical plane and _r_ the point of the pyramid
       terminating in the eye, and _n_ the point of diminution which is
       always in a straight line opposite the eye and always moves as the
       eye moves--just as when a rod is moved its shadow moves, and moves
       with it, precisely as the shadow moves with a body. And each point
       is the apex of a pyramid, all having a common base with the
       intervening vertical plane. But although their bases are equal their
       angles are not equal, because the diminishing point is the
       termination of a smaller angle than that of the eye. If you ask me:
       "By what practical experience can you show me these points?" I
       reply--so far as concerns the diminishing point which moves with you
       --when you walk by a ploughed field look at the straight furrows
       which come down with their ends to the path where you are walking,
       and you will see that each pair of furrows will look as though they
       tried to get nearer and meet at the [farther] end.
       [Footnote: For the easier understanding of the diagram and of its
       connection with the preceding I may here remark that the square
       plane shown above in profile by the line _c s_ is here indicated by
       _e d o p_. According to lines 1, 3 _a b_ must be imagined as a plane
       of glass placed perpendicularly at _o p_.]
       How to measure the pyramid of vision (57)
       57.
       As regards the point in the eye; it is made more intelligible by
       this: If you look into the eye of another person you will see your
       own image. Now imagine 2 lines starting from your ears and going to
       the ears of that image which you see in the other man's eye; you
       will understand that these lines converge in such a way that they
       would meet in a point a little way beyond your own image mirrored in
       the eye. And if you want to measure the diminution of the pyramid in
       the air which occupies the space between the object seen and the
       eye, you must do it according to the diagram figured below. Let _m
       n_ be a tower, and _e f_ a, rod, which you must move backwards and
       forwards till its ends correspond with those of the tower [Footnote
       9: _I sua stremi .. della storre_ (its ends ... of the tower) this
       is the case at _e f_.]; then bring it nearer to the eye, at _c d_
       and you will see that the image of the tower seems smaller, as at _r
       o_. Then [again] bring it closer to the eye and you will see the rod
       project far beyond the image of the tower from _a_ to _b_ and from
       _t_ to _b_, and so you will discern that, a little farther within,
       the lines must converge in a point.
       The Production of pyramid of Vision (58-60)
       58.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       The instant the atmosphere is illuminated it will be filled with an
       infinite number of images which are produced by the various bodies
       and colours assembled in it. And the eye is the target, a loadstone,
       of these images.
       59.
       The whole surface of opaque bodies displays its whole image in all
       the illuminated atmosphere which surrounds them on all sides.
       60.
       That the atmosphere attracts to itself, like a loadstone, all the
       images of the objects that exist in it, and not their forms merely
       but their nature may be clearly seen by the sun, which is a hot and
       luminous body. All the atmosphere, which is the all-pervading
       matter, absorbs light and heat, and reflects in itself the image of
       the source of that heat and splendour and, in each minutest portion,
       does the same. The Northpole does the same as the loadstone shows;
       and the moon and the other planets, without suffering any
       diminution, do the same. Among terrestrial things musk does the same
       and other perfumes.
       61.
       All bodies together, and each by itself, give off to the surrounding
       air an infinite number of images which are all-pervading and each
       complete, each conveying the nature, colour and form of the body
       which produces it.
       It can clearly be shown that all bodies are, by their images,
       all-pervading in the surrounding atmosphere, and each complete in
       itself as to substance form and colour; this is seen by the images
       of the various bodies which are reproduced in one single perforation
       through which they transmit the objects by lines which intersect and
       cause reversed pyramids, from the objects, so that they are upside
       down on the dark plane where they are first reflected. The reason of
       this is--
       [Footnote: The diagram intended to illustrate the statement (Pl. II
       No. i) occurs in the original between lines 3 and 4. The three
       circles must be understood to represent three luminous bodies which
       transmit their images through perforations in a wall into a dark
       chamber, according to a law which is more fully explained in 75?81.
       So far as concerns the present passage the diagram is only intended
       to explain that the images of the three bodies may be made to
       coalesce at any given spot. In the circles are written,
       giallo--yellow, biacho--white, rosso--red.
       The text breaks off at line 8. The paragraph No.40 follows here in
       the original MS.]
       62.
       Every point is the termination of an infinite number of lines, which
       diverge to form a base, and immediately, from the base the same
       lines converge to a pyramid [imaging] both the colour and form. No
       sooner is a form created or compounded than suddenly infinite lines
       and angles are produced from it; and these lines, distributing
       themselves and intersecting each other in the air, give rise to an
       infinite number of angles opposite to each other. Given a base, each
       opposite angle, will form a triangle having a form and proportion
       equal to the larger angle; and if the base goes twice into each of
       the 2 lines of the pyramid the smaller triangle will do the same.
       63.
       Every body in light and shade fills the surrounding air with
       infinite images of itself; and these, by infinite pyramids diffused
       in the air, represent this body throughout space and on every side.
       Each pyramid that is composed of a long assemblage of rays includes
       within itself an infinite number of pyramids and each has the same
       power as all, and all as each. A circle of equidistant pyramids of
       vision will give to their object angles of equal size; and an eye at
       each point will see the object of the same size. The body of the
       atmosphere is full of infinite pyramids composed of radiating
       straight lines, which are produced from the surface of the bodies in
       light and shade, existing in the air; and the farther they are from
       the object which produces them the more acute they become and
       although in their distribution they intersect and cross they never
       mingle together, but pass through all the surrounding air,
       independently converging, spreading, and diffused. And they are all
       of equal power [and value]; all equal to each, and each equal to
       all. By these the images of objects are transmitted through all
       space and in every direction, and each pyramid, in itself, includes,
       in each minutest part, the whole form of the body causing it.
       64.
       The body of the atmosphere is full of infinite radiating pyramids
       produced by the objects existing in it. These intersect and cross
       each other with independent convergence without interfering with
       each other and pass through all the surrounding atmosphere; and are
       of equal force and value--all being equal to each, each to all. And
       by means of these, images of the body are transmitted everywhere and
       on all sides, and each receives in itself every minutest portion of
       the object that produces it.
       Proof by experiment (65-66)
       65.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       The air is filled with endless images of the objects distributed in
       it; and all are represented in all, and all in one, and all in each,
       whence it happens that if two mirrors are placed in such a manner as
       to face each other exactly, the first will be reflected in the
       second and the second in the first. The first being reflected in the
       second takes to it the image of itself with all the images
       represented in it, among which is the image of the second mirror,
       and so, image within image, they go on to infinity in such a manner
       as that each mirror has within it a mirror, each smaller than the
       last and one inside the other. Thus, by this example, it is clearly
       proved that every object sends its image to every spot whence the
       object itself can be seen; and the converse: That the same object
       may receive in itself all the images of the objects that are in
       front of it. Hence the eye transmits through the atmosphere its own
       image to all the objects that are in front of it and receives them
       into itself, that is to say on its surface, whence they are taken in
       by the common sense, which considers them and if they are pleasing
       commits them to the memory. Whence I am of opinion: That the
       invisible images in the eyes are produced towards the object, as the
       image of the object to the eye. That the images of the objects must
       be disseminated through the air. An instance may be seen in several
       mirrors placed in a circle, which will reflect each other endlessly.
       When one has reached the other it is returned to the object that
       produced it, and thence--being diminished--it is returned again to
       the object and then comes back once more, and this happens
       endlessly. If you put a light between two flat mirrors with a
       distance of 1 braccio between them you will see in each of them an
       infinite number of lights, one smaller than another, to the last. If
       at night you put a light between the walls of a room, all the parts
       of that wall will be tinted with the image of that light. And they
       will receive the light and the light will fall on them, mutually,
       that is to say, when there is no obstacle to interrupt the
       transmission of the images. This same example is seen in a greater
       degree in the distribution of the solar rays which all together, and
       each by itself, convey to the object the image of the body which
       causes it. That each body by itself alone fills with its images the
       atmosphere around it, and that the same air is able, at the same
       time, to receive the images of the endless other objects which are
       in it, this is clearly proved by these examples. And every object is
       everywhere visible in the whole of the atmosphere, and the whole in
       every smallest part of it; and all the objects in the whole, and all
       in each smallest part; each in all and all in every part.
       66.
       The images of objects are all diffused through the atmosphere which
       receives them; and all on every side in it. To prove this, let _a c
       e_ be objects of which the images are admitted to a dark chamber by
       the small holes _n p_ and thrown upon the plane _f i_ opposite to
       these holes. As many images will be produced in the chamber on the
       plane as the number of the said holes.
       General conclusions (67)
       67.
       All objects project their whole image and likeness, diffused and
       mingled in the whole of the atmosphere, opposite to themselves. The
       image of every point of the bodily surface, exists in every part of
       the atmosphere. All the images of the objects are in every part of
       the atmosphere. The whole, and each part of the image of the
       atmosphere is [reflected] in each point of the surface of the bodies
       presented to it. Therefore both the part and the whole of the images
       of the objects exist, both in the whole and in the parts of the
       surface of these visible bodies. Whence we may evidently say that
       the image of each object exists, as a whole and in every part, in
       each part and in the whole interchangeably in every existing body.
       As is seen in two mirrors placed opposite to each other.
       That the contrary is impossible (68)
       68.
       It is impossible that the eye should project from itself, by visual
       rays, the visual virtue, since, as soon as it opens, that front
       portion [of the eye] which would give rise to this emanation would
       have to go forth to the object and this it could not do without
       time. And this being so, it could not travel so high as the sun in a
       month's time when the eye wanted to see it. And if it could reach
       the sun it would necessarily follow that it should perpetually
       remain in a continuous line from the eye to the sun and should
       always diverge in such a way as to form between the sun and the eye
       the base and the apex of a pyramid. This being the case, if the eye
       consisted of a million worlds, it would not prevent its being
       consumed in the projection of its virtue; and if this virtue would
       have to travel through the air as perfumes do, the winds would bent
       it and carry it into another place. But we do [in fact] see the mass
       of the sun with the same rapidity as [an object] at the distance of
       a braccio, and the power of sight is not disturbed by the blowing of
       the winds nor by any other accident.
       [Footnote: The view here refuted by Leonardo was maintained among
       others by Bramantino, Leonardo's Milanese contemporary. LOMAZZO
       writes as follows in his Trattato dell' Arte della pittura &c.
       (Milano 1584. Libr. V cp. XXI): Sovviemmi di aver gia letto in certi
       scritti alcune cose di Bramantino milanese, celebratissimo pittore,
       attenente alla prospettiva, le quali ho voluto riferire, e quasi
       intessere in questo luogo, affinche sappiamo qual fosse l'opinione
       di cosi chiaro e famoso pittore intorno alla prospettiva . . Scrive
       Bramantino che la prospettiva e una cosa che contrafa il naturale, e
       che cio si fa in tre modi
       Circa il primo modo che si fa con ragione, per essere la cosa in
       poche parole conclusa da Bramantino in maniera che giudico non
       potersi dir meglio, contenendovi si tutta Parte del principio al
       fine, io riferiro per appunto le proprie parole sue (cp. XXII, Prima
       prospettiva di Bramantino). La prima prospettiva fa le cose di
       punto, e l'altra non mai, e la terza piu appresso. Adunque la prima
       si dimanda prospettiva, cioe ragione, la quale fa l'effetto dell'
       occhio, facendo crescere e calare secondo gli effetti degli occhi.
       Questo crescere e calare non procede della cosa propria, che in se
       per esser lontana, ovvero vicina, per quello effetto non puo
       crescere e sminuire, ma procede dagli effetti degli occhi, i quali
       sono piccioli, e percio volendo vedere tanto gran cosa_, bisogna che
       mandino fuora la virtu visiva, _la quale si dilata in tanta
       larghezza, che piglia tutto quello che vuoi vedere, ed_ arrivando a
       quella cosa la vede dove e: _e da lei agli occhi per quello circuito
       fino all' occhio, e tutto quello termine e pieno di quella cosa_.
       It is worthy of note that Leonardo had made his memorandum refuting
       this view, at Milan in 1492]
       A parallel case (69)
       69.
       Just as a stone flung into the water becomes the centre and cause of
       many circles, and as sound diffuses itself in circles in the air: so
       any object, placed in the luminous atmosphere, diffuses itself in
       circles, and fills the surrounding air with infinite images of
       itself. And is repeated, the whole every-where, and the whole in
       every smallest part. This can be proved by experiment, since if you
       shut a window that faces west and make a hole [Footnote: 6. Here the
       text breaks off.] . .
       [Footnote: Compare LIBRI, _Histoire des sciences mathematiques en
       Italie_. Tome III, p. 43.]
       The function of the eye as explained by the camera obscura (70-71)
       70.
       If the object in front of the eye sends its image to the eye, the
       eye, on the other hand, sends its image to the object, and no
       portion whatever of the object is lost in the images it throws off,
       for any reason either in the eye or the object. Therefore we may
       rather believe it to be the nature and potency of our luminous
       atmosphere which absorbs the images of the objects existing in it,
       than the nature of the objects, to send their images through the
       air. If the object opposite to the eye were to send its image to the
       eye, the eye would have to do the same to the object, whence it
       might seem that these images were an emanation. But, if so, it would
       be necessary [to admit] that every object became rapidly smaller;
       because each object appears by its images in the surrounding
       atmosphere. That is: the whole object in the whole atmosphere, and
       in each part; and all the objects in the whole atmosphere and all of
       them in each part; speaking of that atmosphere which is able to
       contain in itself the straight and radiating lines of the images
       projected by the objects. From this it seems necessary to admit that
       it is in the nature of the atmosphere, which subsists between the
       objects, and which attracts the images of things to itself like a
       loadstone, being placed between them.
       PROVE HOW ALL OBJECTS, PLACED IN ONE POSITION, ARE ALL EVERYWHERE
       AND ALL IN EACH PART.
       I say that if the front of a building--or any open piazza or
       field--which is illuminated by the sun has a dwelling opposite to
       it, and if, in the front which does not face the sun, you make a
       small round hole, all the illuminated objects will project their
       images through that hole and be visible inside the dwelling on the
       opposite wall which may be made white; and there, in fact, they will
       be upside down, and if you make similar openings in several places
       in the same wall you will have the same result from each. Hence the
       images of the illuminated objects are all everywhere on this wall
       and all in each minutest part of it. The reason, as we clearly know,
       is that this hole must admit some light to the said dwelling, and
       the light admitted by it is derived from one or many luminous
       bodies. If these bodies are of various colours and shapes the rays
       forming the images are of various colours and shapes, and so will
       the representations be on the wall.
       [Footnote: 70. 15--23. This section has already been published in the
       "_Saggio delle Opere di Leonardo da Vinci_" Milan 1872, pp. 13, 14.
       G. Govi observes upon it, that Leonardo is not to be regarded as the
       inventor of the Camera obscura, but that he was the first to explain
       by it the structure of the eye. An account of the Camera obscura
       first occurs in CESARE CESARINI's Italian version of Vitruvius, pub.
       1523, four years after Leonardo's death. Cesarini expressly names
       Benedettino Don Papnutio as the inventor of the Camera obscura. In
       his explanation of the function of the eye by a comparison with the
       Camera obscura Leonardo was the precursor of G. CARDANO, Professor
       of Medicine at Bologna (died 1576) and it appears highly probable
       that this is, in fact, the very discovery which Leonardo ascribes to
       himself in section 21 without giving any further details.]
       71.
       HOW THE IMAGES OF OBJECTS RECEIVED BY THE EYE INTERSECT WITHIN THE
       CRYSTALLINE HUMOUR OF THE EYE.
       An experiment, showing how objects transmit their images or
       pictures, intersecting within the eye in the crystalline humour, is
       seen when by some small round hole penetrate the images of
       illuminated objects into a very dark chamber. Then, receive these
       images on a white paper placed within this dark room and rather near
       to the hole and you will see all the objects on the paper in their
       proper forms and colours, but much smaller; and they will be upside
       down by reason of that very intersection. These images being
       transmitted from a place illuminated by the sun will seem actually
       painted on this paper which must be extremely thin and looked at
       from behind. And let the little perforation be made in a very thin
       plate of iron. Let _a b e d e_ be the object illuminated by the sun
       and _o r_ the front of the dark chamber in which is the said hole at
       _n m_. Let _s t_ be the sheet of paper intercepting the rays of the
       images of these objects upside down, because the rays being
       straight, _a_ on the right hand becomes _k_ on the left, and _e_ on
       the left becomes _f_ on the right; and the same takes place inside
       the pupil.
       [Footnote: This chapter is already known through a translation into
       French by VENTURI. Compare his '_Essai sur les ouvrages
       physico-mathematiques de L. da Vinci avec des fragments tires de ses
       Manuscrits, apportes de l'Italie. Lu a la premiere classe de
       l'Institut national des Sciences et Arts.' Paris, An V_ (1797).]
       The practice of perspective (72-73)
       72.
       In the practice of perspective the same rules apply to light and to
       the eye.
       73.
       The object which is opposite to the pupil of the eye is seen by that
       pupil and that which is opposite to the eye is seen by the pupil.
       Refraction of the rays falling upon the eye (74-75)
       74.
       The lines sent forth by the image of an object to the eye do not
       reach the point within the eye in straight lines.
       75.
       If the judgment of the eye is situated within it, the straight lines
       of the images are refracted on its surface because they pass through
       the rarer to the denser medium. If, when you are under water, you
       look at objects in the air you will see them out of their true
       place; and the same with objects under water seen from the air.
       The inversion of the images (76)
       All the images of objects which pass through a window [glass pane]
       from the free outer air to the air confined within walls, are seen
       on the opposite side; and an object which moves in the outer air
       from east to west will seem in its shadow, on the wall which is
       lighted by this confined air, to have an opposite motion.
       The intersection of the rays (77-82)
       77.
       THE PRINCIPLE ON WHICH THE IMAGES OF BODIES PASS IN BETWEEN THE
       MARGINS OF THE OPENINGS BY WHICH THEY ENTER.
       What difference is there in the way in which images pass through
       narrow openings and through large openings, or in those which pass
       by the sides of shaded bodies? By moving the edges of the opening
       through which the images are admitted, the images of immovable
       objects are made to move. And this happens, as is shown in the 9th
       which demonstrates: [Footnote 11: _per la 9a che dicie_. When
       Leonardo refers thus to a number it serves to indicate marginal
       diagrams; this can in some instances be distinctly proved. The ninth
       sketch on the page W. L. 145 b corresponds to the middle sketch of
       the three reproduced.] the images of any object are all everywhere,
       and all in each part of the surrounding air. It follows that if one
       of the edges of the hole by which the images are admitted to a dark
       chamber is moved it cuts off those rays of the image that were in
       contact with it and gets nearer to other rays which previously were
       remote from it &c.
       OF THE MOVEMENT OF THE EDGE AT THE RIGHT OR LEFT, OR THE UPPER, OR
       LOWER EDGE.
       If you move the right side of the opening the image on the left will
       move [being that] of the object which entered on the right side of
       the opening; and the same result will happen with all the other
       sides of the opening. This can be proved by the 2nd of this which
       shows: all the rays which convey the images of objects through the
       air are straight lines. Hence, if the images of very large bodies
       have to pass through very small holes, and beyond these holes
       recover their large size, the lines must necessarily intersect.
       [Footnote: 77. 2. In the first of the three diagrams Leonardo had
       drawn only one of the two margins, et _m_.]
       78.
       Necessity has provided that all the images of objects in front of
       the eye shall intersect in two places. One of these intersections is
       in the pupil, the other in the crystalline lens; and if this were
       not the case the eye could not see so great a number of objects as
       it does. This can be proved, since all the lines which intersect do
       so in a point. Because nothing is seen of objects excepting their
       surface; and their edges are lines, in contradistinction to the
       definition of a surface. And each minute part of a line is equal to
       a point; for _smallest_ is said of that than which nothing can be
       smaller, and this definition is equivalent to the definition of the
       point. Hence it is possible for the whole circumference of a circle
       to transmit its image to the point of intersection, as is shown in
       the 4th of this which shows: all the smallest parts of the images
       cross each other without interfering with each other. These
       demonstrations are to illustrate the eye. No image, even of the
       smallest object, enters the eye without being turned upside down;
       but as it penetrates into the crystalline lens it is once more
       reversed and thus the image is restored to the same position within
       the eye as that of the object outside the eye.
       79.
       OF THE CENTRAL LINE OF THE EYE.
       Only one line of the image, of all those that reach the visual
       virtue, has no intersection; and this has no sensible dimensions
       because it is a mathematical line which originates from a
       mathematical point, which has no dimensions.
       According to my adversary, necessity requires that the central line
       of every image that enters by small and narrow openings into a dark
       chamber shall be turned upside down, together with the images of the
       bodies that surround it.
       80.
       AS TO WHETHER THE CENTRAL LINE OF THE IMAGE CAN BE INTERSECTED, OR
       NOT, WITHIN THE OPENING.
       It is impossible that the line should intersect itself; that is,
       that its right should cross over to its left side, and so, its left
       side become its right side. Because such an intersection demands two
       lines, one from each side; for there can be no motion from right to
       left or from left to right in itself without such extension and
       thickness as admit of such motion. And if there is extension it is
       no longer a line but a surface, and we are investigating the
       properties of a line, and not of a surface. And as the line, having
       no centre of thickness cannot be divided, we must conclude that the
       line can have no sides to intersect each other. This is proved by
       the movement of the line _a f_ to _a b_ and of the line _e b_ to _e
       f_, which are the sides of the surface _a f e b_. But if you move
       the line _a b_ and the line _e f_, with the frontends _a e_, to the
       spot _c_, you will have moved the opposite ends _f b_ towards each
       other at the point _d_. And from the two lines you will have drawn
       the straight line _c d_ which cuts the middle of the intersection of
       these two lines at the point _n_ without any intersection. For, you
       imagine these two lines as having breadth, it is evident that by
       this motion the first will entirely cover the other--being equal
       with it--without any intersection, in the position _c d_. And this
       is sufficient to prove our proposition.
       81.
       HOW THE INNUMERABLE RAYS FROM INNUMERABLE IMAGES CAN CONVERGE TO A POINT.
       Just as all lines can meet at a point without interfering with each
       other--being without breadth or thickness--in the same way all the
       images of surfaces can meet there; and as each given point faces the
       object opposite to it and each object faces an opposite point, the
       converging rays of the image can pass through the point and diverge
       again beyond it to reproduce and re-magnify the real size of that
       image. But their impressions will appear reversed--as is shown in
       the first, above; where it is said that every image intersects as it
       enters the narrow openings made in a very thin substance.
       Read the marginal text on the other side.
       In proportion as the opening is smaller than the shaded body, so
       much less will the images transmitted through this opening intersect
       each other. The sides of images which pass through openings into a
       dark room intersect at a point which is nearer to the opening in
       proportion as the opening is narrower. To prove this let _a b_ be an
       object in light and shade which sends not its shadow but the image
       of its darkened form through the opening _d e_ which is as wide as
       this shaded body; and its sides _a b_, being straight lines (as has
       been proved) must intersect between the shaded object and the
       opening; but nearer to the opening in proportion as it is smaller
       than the object in shade. As is shown, on your right hand and your
       left hand, in the two diagrams _a_ _b_ _c_ _n_ _m_ _o_ where, the
       right opening _d_ _e_, being equal in width to the shaded object _a_
       _b_, the intersection of the sides of the said shaded object occurs
       half way between the opening and the shaded object at the point _c_.
       But this cannot happen in the left hand figure, the opening _o_
       being much smaller than the shaded object _n_ _m_.
       It is impossible that the images of objects should be seen between
       the objects and the openings through which the images of these
       bodies are admitted; and this is plain, because where the atmosphere
       is illuminated these images are not formed visibly.
       When the images are made double by mutually crossing each other they
       are invariably doubly as dark in tone. To prove this let _d_ _e_ _h_
       be such a doubling which although it is only seen within the space
       between the bodies in _b_ and _i_ this will not hinder its being
       seen from _f_ _g_ or from _f_ _m_; being composed of the images _a_
       _b_ _i_ _k_ which run together in _d_ _e_ _h_.
       [Footnote: 81. On the original diagram at the beginning of this
       chapter Leonardo has written "_azurro_" (blue) where in the
       facsimile I have marked _A_, and "_giallo_" (yellow) where _B_
       stands.]
       [Footnote: 15--23. These lines stand between the diagrams I and III.]
       [Footnote: 24--53. These lines stand between the diagrams I and II.]
       [Footnote: 54--97 are written along the left side of diagram I.]
       82.
       An experiment showing that though the pupil may not be moved from
       its position the objects seen by it may appear to move from their
       places.
       If you look at an object at some distance from you and which is
       below the eye, and fix both your eyes upon it and with one hand
       firmly hold the upper lid open while with the other you push up the
       under lid--still keeping your eyes fixed on the object gazed at--you
       will see that object double; one [image] remaining steady, and the
       other moving in a contrary direction to the pressure of your finger
       on the lower eyelid. How false the opinion is of those who say that
       this happens because the pupil of the eye is displaced from its
       position.
       How the above mentioned facts prove that the pupil acts upside down
       in seeing.
       [Footnote: 82. 14--17. The subject indicated by these two headings is
       fully discussed in the two chapters that follow them in the
       original; but it did not seem to me appropriate to include them
       here.]
       Demostration of perspective by means of a vertical glass plane (83-85)
       83.
       OF THE PLANE OF GLASS.
       Perspective is nothing else than seeing place [or objects] behind a
       plane of glass, quite transparent, on the surface of which the
       objects behind that glass are to be drawn. These can be traced in
       pyramids to the point in the eye, and these pyramids are intersected
       on the glass plane.
       84.
       Pictorial perspective can never make an object at the same distance,
       look of the same size as it appears to the eye. You see that the
       apex of the pyramid _f c d_ is as far from the object _c_ _d_ as the
       same point _f_ is from the object _a_ _b_; and yet _c_ _d_, which is
       the base made by the painter's point, is smaller than _a_ _b_ which
       is the base of the lines from the objects converging in the eye and
       refracted at _s_ _t_, the surface of the eye. This may be proved by
       experiment, by the lines of vision and then by the lines of the
       painter's plumbline by cutting the real lines of vision on one and
       the same plane and measuring on it one and the same object.
       85.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       The vertical plane is a perpendicular line, imagined as in front of
       the central point where the apex of the pyramids converge. And this
       plane bears the same relation to this point as a plane of glass
       would, through which you might see the various objects and draw them
       on it. And the objects thus drawn would be smaller than the
       originals, in proportion as the distance between the glass and the
       eye was smaller than that between the glass and the objects.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       The different converging pyramids produced by the objects, will
       show, on the plane, the various sizes and remoteness of the objects
       causing them.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       All those horizontal planes of which the extremes are met by
       perpendicular lines forming right angles, if they are of equal width
       the more they rise to the level of eye the less this is seen, and
       the more the eye is above them the more will their real width be
       seen.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       The farther a spherical body is from the eye the more you will see of it.
       The angle of sight varies with the distance (86-88)
       86.
       A simple and natural method; showing how objects appear to the eye
       without any other medium.
       The object that is nearest to the eye always seems larger than
       another of the same size at greater distance. The eye _m_, seeing
       the spaces _o v x_, hardly detects the difference between them, and
       the. reason of this is that it is close to them [Footnote 6: It is
       quite inconceivable to me why M. RAVAISSON, in a note to his French
       translation of this simple passage should have remarked: _Il est
       clair que c'est par erreur que Leonard a ecrit_ per esser visino _au
       lieu de_ per non esser visino. (See his printed ed. of MS. A. p.
       38.)]; but if these spaces are marked on the vertical plane _n o_
       the space _o v_ will be seen at _o r_, and in the same way the space
       _v x_ will appear at _r q_. And if you carry this out in any place
       where you can walk round, it will look out of proportion by reason
       of the great difference in the spaces _o r_ and _r q_. And this
       proceeds from the eye being so much below [near] the plane that the
       plane is foreshortened. Hence, if you wanted to carry it out, you
       would have [to arrange] to see the perspective through a single hole
       which must be at the point _m_, or else you must go to a distance of
       at least 3 times the height of the object you see. The plane _o p_
       being always equally remote from the eye will reproduce the objects
       in a satisfactory way, so that they may be seen from place to place.
       87.
       How every large mass sends forth its images, which may diminish
       through infinity.
       The images of any large mass being infinitely divisible may be
       infinitely diminished.
       88.
       Objects of equal size, situated in various places, will be seen by
       different pyramids which will each be smaller in proportion as the
       object is farther off.
       Opposite pyramids in juxtaposition (89)
       89.
       Perspective, in dealing with distances, makes use of two opposite
       pyramids, one of which has its apex in the eye and the base as
       distant as the horizon. The other has the base towards the eye and
       the apex on the horizon. Now, the first includes the [visible]
       universe, embracing all the mass of the objects that lie in front of
       the eye; as it might be a vast landscape seen through a very small
       opening; for the more remote the objects are from the eye, the
       greater number can be seen through the opening, and thus the pyramid
       is constructed with the base on the horizon and the apex in the eye,
       as has been said. The second pyramid is extended to a spot which is
       smaller in proportion as it is farther from the eye; and this second
       perspective [= pyramid] results from the first.
       On simple and complex perspective (90)
       SIMPLE PERSPECTIVE.
       Simple perspective is that which is constructed by art on a vertical
       plane which is equally distant from the eye in every part. Complex
       perspective is that which is constructed on a ground-plan in which
       none of the parts are equally distant from the eye.
       The proper distance of objects from the eye (91-92)
       91.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       No surface can be seen exactly as it is, if the eye that sees it is
       not equally remote from all its edges.
       92.
       WHY WHEN AN OBJECT IS PLACED CLOSE TO THE EYE ITS EDGES ARE
       INDISTINCT.
       When an object opposite the eye is brought too close to it, its
       edges must become too confused to be distinguished; as it happens
       with objects close to a light, which cast a large and indistinct
       shadow, so is it with an eye which estimates objects opposite to it;
       in all cases of linear perspective, the eye acts in the same way as
       the light. And the reason is that the eye has one leading line (of
       vision) which dilates with distance and embraces with true
       discernment large objects at a distance as well as small ones that
       are close. But since the eye sends out a multitude of lines which
       surround this chief central one and since these which are farthest
       from the centre in this cone of lines are less able to discern with
       accuracy, it follows that an object brought close to the eye is not
       at a due distance, but is too near for the central line to be able
       to discern the outlines of the object. So the edges fall within the
       lines of weaker discerning power, and these are to the function of
       the eye like dogs in the chase which can put up the game but cannot
       take it. Thus these cannot take in the objects, but induce the
       central line of sight to turn upon them, when they have put them up.
       Hence the objects which are seen with these lines of sight have
       confused outlines.
       The relative size of objects with regard to their distance from the eye (93-98)
       93.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       Small objects close at hand and large ones at a distance, being seen
       within equal angles, will appear of the same size.
       94.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       There is no object so large but that at a great distance from the
       eye it does not appear smaller than a smaller object near.
       95.
       Among objects of equal size that which is most remote from the eye
       will look the smallest. [Footnote: This axiom, sufficiently clear in
       itself, is in the original illustrated by a very large diagram,
       constructed like that here reproduced under No. 108.
       The same idea is repeated in C. A. I a; I a, stated as follows:
       _Infra le cose d'equal grandeza quella si dimostra di minor figura
       che sara piu distante dall' ochio_.--]
       96.
       Why an object is less distinct when brought near to the eye, and why
       with spectacles, or without the naked eye sees badly either close or
       far off [as the case may be].
       97.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       Among objects of equal size, that which is most remote from the eye
       will look the smallest.
       98.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       No second object can be so much lower than the first as that the eye
       will not see it higher than the first, if the eye is above the
       second.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       And this second object will never be so much higher than the first
       as that the eye, being below them, will not see the second as lower
       than the first.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       If the eye sees a second square through the centre of a smaller one,
       that is nearer, the second, larger square will appear to be
       surrounded by the smaller one.
       PERSPECTIVE--PROPOSITION.
       Objects that are farther off can never be so large but that those in
       front, though smaller, will conceal or surround them.
       DEFINITION.
       This proposition can be proved by experiment. For if you look
       through a small hole there is nothing so large that it cannot be
       seen through it and the object so seen appears surrounded and
       enclosed by the outline of the sides of the hole. And if you stop it
       up, this small stopping will conceal the view of the largest object.
       The apparent size of objects defined by calculation (99-105)
       99.
       OF LINEAR PERSPECTIVE.
       Linear Perspective deals with the action of the lines of sight, in
       proving by measurement how much smaller is a second object than the
       first, and how much the third is smaller than the second; and so on
       by degrees to the end of things visible. I find by experience that
       if a second object is as far beyond the first as the first is from
       the eye, although they are of the same size, the second will seem
       half the size of the first and if the third object is of the same
       size as the 2nd, and the 3rd is as far beyond the second as the 2nd
       from the first, it will appear of half the size of the second; and
       so on by degrees, at equal distances, the next farthest will be half
       the size of the former object. So long as the space does not exceed
       the length of 20 braccia. But, beyond 20 braccia figures of equal
       size will lose 2/4 and at 40 braccia they will lose 9/10, and 19/20
       at 60 braccia, and so on diminishing by degrees. This is if the
       picture plane is distant from you twice your own height. If it is
       only as far off as your own height, there will be a great difference
       between the first braccia and the second.
       [Footnote: This chapter is included in DUFRESNE'S and MANZI'S
       editions of the Treatise on Painting. H. LUDWIG, in his commentary,
       calls this chapter "_eines der wichtigsten im ganzen Tractat_", but
       at the same time he asserts that its substance has been so
       completely disfigured in the best MS. copies that we ought not to
       regard Leonardo as responsible for it. However, in the case of this
       chapter, the old MS. copies agree with the original as it is
       reproduced above. From the chapters given later in this edition,
       which were written at a subsequent date, it would appear that
       Leonardo corrected himself on these points.]
       100.
       OF THE DIMINUTION OF OBJECTS AT VARIOUS DISTANCES.
       A second object as far distant from the first as the first is from
       the eye will appear half the size of the first, though they be of
       the same size really.
       OF THE DEGREES OF DIMINUTION.
       If you place the vertical plane at one braccio from the eye, the
       first object, being at a distance of 4 braccia from your eye will
       diminish to 3/4 of its height at that plane; and if it is 8 braccia
       from the eye, to 7/8; and if it is 16 braccia off, it will diminish
       to 15/16 of its height and so on by degrees, as the space doubles
       the diminution will double.
       101.
       Begin from the line _m f_ with the eye below; then go up and do the
       same with the line _n f_, then with the eye above and close to the 2
       gauges on the ground look at _m n_; then as _c m_ is to _m n_ so
       will _n m_ be to _n s_.
       If _a n_ goes 3 times into _f b, m p_ will do the same into _p g_.
       Then go backwards so far as that _c d_ goes twice into _a n_ and _p
       g_ will be equal to _g h_. And _m p_ will go into _h p_ as often as
       _d c_ into _o p_.
       [Footnote: The first three lines are unfortunately very obscure.]
       102.
       I GIVE THE DEGREES OF THE OBJECTS SEEN BY THE EYE AS THE MUSICIAN
       DOES THE NOTES HEARD BY THE EAR.
       Although the objects seen by the eye do, in fact, touch each other
       as they recede, I will nevertheless found my rule on spaces of 20
       braccia each; as a musician does with notes, which, though they can
       be carried on one into the next, he divides into degrees from note
       to note calling them 1st, 2nd, 3rd, 4th, 5th; and has affixed a name
       to each degree in raising or lowering the voice.
       103.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       Let _f_ be the level and distance of the eye; and _a_ the vertical
       plane, as high as a man; let _e_ be a man, then I say that on the
       plane this will be the distance from the plane to the 2nd man.
       104.
       The differences in the diminution of objects of equal size in
       consequence of their various remoteness from the eye will bear among
       themselves the same proportions as those of the spaces between the
       eye and the different objects.
       Find out how much a man diminishes at a certain distance and what
       its length is; and then at twice that distance and at 3 times, and
       so make your general rule.
       105.
       The eye cannot judge where an object high up ought to descend.
       106.
       PERSPECTIVE.
       If two similar and equal objects are placed one beyond the other at
       a given distance the difference in their size will appear greater in
       proportion as they are nearer to the eye that sees them. And
       conversely there will seem to be less difference in their size in
       proportion as they are remote from the eve.
       This is proved by the proportions of their distances among
       themselves; for, if the first of these two objects were as far from
       the eye, as the 2nd from the first this would be called the second
       proportion: since, if the first is at 1 braccia from the eye and the
       2nd at two braccia, two being twice as much as one, the first object
       will look twice as large as the second. But if you place the first
       at a hundred braccia from you and the second at a hundred and one,
       you will find that the first is only so much larger than the second
       as 100 is less than 101; and the converse is equally true. And
       again, the same thing is proved by the 4th of this book which shows
       that among objects that are equal, there is the same proportion in
       the diminution of the size as in the increase in the distance from
       the eye of the spectator.
       On natural perspective (107--109)
       107.
       OF EQUAL OBJECTS THE MOST REMOTE LOOK THE SMALLEST.
       The practice of perspective may be divided into ... parts [Footnote
       4: _in_ ... _parte_. The space for the number is left blank in the
       original.], of which the first treats of objects seen by the eye at
       any distance; and it shows all these objects just as the eye sees
       them diminished, without obliging a man to stand in one place rather
       than another so long as the plane does not produce a second
       foreshortening.
       But the second practice is a combination of perspective derived
       partly from art and partly from nature and the work done by its
       rules is in every portion of it, influenced by natural perspective
       and artificial perspective. By natural perspective I mean that the
       plane on which this perspective is represented is a flat surface,
       and this plane, although it is parallel both in length and height,
       is forced to diminish in its remoter parts more than in its nearer
       ones. And this is proved by the first of what has been said above,
       and its diminution is natural. But artificial perspective, that is
       that which is devised by art, does the contrary; for objects equal
       in size increase on the plane where it is foreshortened in
       proportion as the eye is more natural and nearer to the plane, and
       as the part of the plane on which it is figured is farther from the
       eye.
       And let this plane be _d e_ on which are seen 3 equal circles which
       are beyond this plane _d e_, that is the circles _a b c_. Now you
       see that the eye _h_ sees on the vertical plane the sections of the
       images, largest of those that are farthest and smallest of the
       nearest.
       108.
       Here follows what is wanting in the margin at the foot on the other
       side of this page.
       Natural perspective acts in a contrary way; for, at greater
       distances the object seen appears smaller, and at a smaller distance
       the object appears larger. But this said invention requires the
       spectator to stand with his eye at a small hole and then, at that
       small hole, it will be very plain. But since many (men's) eyes
       endeavour at the same time to see one and the same picture produced
       by this artifice only one can see clearly the effect of this
       perspective and all the others will see confusion. It is well
       therefore to avoid such complex perspective and hold to simple
       perspective which does not regard planes as foreshortened, but as
       much as possible in their proper form. This simple perspective, in
       which the plane intersects the pyramids by which the images are
       conveyed to the eye at an equal distance from the eye is our
       constant experience, from the curved form of the pupil of the eye on
       which the pyramids are intersected at an equal distance from the
       visual virtue.
       [Footnote 24: _la prima di sopra_ i. e. the first of the three
       diagrams which, in the original MS., are placed in the margin at the
       beginning of this chapter.]
       109.
       OF A MIXTURE OF NATURAL AND ARTIFICIAL PERSPECTIVE.
       This diagram distinguishes natural from artificial perspective. But
       before proceeding any farther I will define what is natural and what
       is artificial perspective. Natural perspective says that the more
       remote of a series of objects of equal size will look the smaller,
       and conversely, the nearer will look the larger and the apparent
       size will diminish in proportion to the distance. But in artificial
       perspective when objects of unequal size are placed at various
       distances, the smallest is nearer to the eye than the largest and
       the greatest distance looks as though it were the least of all; and
       the cause of this is the plane on which the objects are represented;
       and which is at unequal distances from the eye throughout its
       length. And this diminution of the plane is natural, but the
       perspective shown upon it is artificial since it nowhere agrees with
       the true diminution of the said plane. Whence it follows, that when
       the eye is somewhat removed from the [station point of the]
       perspective that it has been gazing at, all the objects represented
       look monstrous, and this does not occur in natural perspective,
       which has been defined above. Let us say then, that the square _a b
       c d_ figured above is foreshortened being seen by the eye situated
       in the centre of the side which is in front. But a mixture of
       artificial and natural perspective will be seen in this tetragon
       called _el main_ [Footnote 20: _el main_ is quite legibly written in
       the original; the meaning and derivation of the word are equally
       doubtful.], that is to say _e f g h_ which must appear to the eye of
       the spectator to be equal to _a b c d_ so long as the eye remains in
       its first position between _c_ and _d_. And this will be seen to
       have a good effect, because the natural perspective of the plane
       will conceal the defects which would [otherwise] seem monstrous. _