您的位置 : 首页 > 英文著作
Proposed Roads To Freedom
PART I - HISTORICAL   PART I - HISTORICAL - CHAPTER II - BAKUNIN AND ANARCHISM
Bertrand Russell
下载:Proposed Roads To Freedom.txt
本书全文检索:
       _ CHAPTER II - BAKUNIN AND ANARCHISM
       IN the popular mind, an Anarchist is a person
       who throws bombs and commits other outrages,
       either because he is more or less insane, or because
       he uses the pretense of extreme political opinions as
       a cloak for criminal proclivities. This view is, of
       course, in every way inadequate. Some Anarchists
       believe in throwing bombs; many do not. Men of
       almost every other shade of opinion believe in throwing
       bombs in suitable circumstances: for example,
       the men who threw the bomb at Sarajevo which
       started the present war were not Anarchists, but
       Nationalists. And those Anarchists who are in
       favor of bomb-throwing do not in this respect differ
       on any vital principle from the rest of the community,
       with the exception of that infinitesimal portion
       who adopt the Tolstoyan attitude of non-resistance.
       Anarchists, like Socialists, usually believe
       in the doctrine of the class war, and if they use
       bombs, it is as Governments use bombs, for purposes
       of war: but for every bomb manufactured by an
       Anarchist, many millions are manufactured by Governments,
       and for every man killed by Anarchist
       violence, many millions are killed by the violence of
       States. We may, therefore, dismiss from our minds
       the whole question of violence, which plays so large
       a part in the popular imagination, since it is neither
       essential nor peculiar to those who adopt the Anarchist
       position.
       Anarchism, as its derivation indicates, is the
       theory which is opposed to every kind of forcible
       government. It is opposed to the State as the
       embodiment of the force employed in the government
       of the community. Such government as Anarchism
       can tolerate must be free government, not merely in
       the sense that it is that of a majority, but in the sense
       that it is that assented to by all. Anarchists object
       to such institutions as the police and the criminal
       law, by means of which the will of one part of the
       community is forced upon another part. In their
       view, the democratic form of government is not very
       enormously preferable to other forms so long as
       minorities are compelled by force or its potentiality
       to submit to the will of majorities. Liberty is the
       supreme good in the Anarchist creed, and liberty
       is sought by the direct road of abolishing all forcible
       control over the individual by the community.
       Anarchism, in this sense, is no new doctrine. It
       is set forth admirably by Chuang Tzu, a Chinese philosopher,
       who lived about the year 300 B. C.:--
       Horses have hoofs to carry them over frost and snow;
       hair, to protect them from wind and cold. They eat grass
       and drink water, and fling up their heels over the champaign.
       Such is the real nature of horses. Palatial
       dwellings are of no use to them.
       One day Po Lo appeared, saying: "I understand the
       management of horses."
       So he branded them, and clipped them, and pared
       their hoofs, and put halters on them, tying them up by
       the head and shackling them by the feet, and disposing
       them in stables, with the result that two or three in
       every ten died. Then he kept them hungry and thirsty,
       trotting them and galloping them, and grooming, and
       trimming, with the misery of the tasselled bridle before
       and the fear of the knotted whip behind, until more than
       half of them were dead.
       The potter says: "I can do what I will with Clay.
       If I want it round, I use compasses; if rectangular, a
       square."
       The carpenter says: "I can do what I will with
       wood. If I want it curved, I use an arc; if straight, a
       line."
       But on what grounds can we think that the natures
       of clay and wood desire this application of compasses and
       square, of arc and line? Nevertheless, every age extols
       Po Lo for his skill in managing horses, and potters and
       carpenters for their skill with clay and wood. Those
       who govern the empire make the same mistake.
       Now I regard government of the empire from quite
       a different point of view.
       The people have certain natural instincts:--to weave
       and clothe themselves, to till and feed themselves. These
       are common to all humanity, and all are agreed thereon.
       Such instincts are called "Heaven-sent."
       And so in the days when natural instincts prevailed,
       men moved quietly and gazed steadily. At that time
       there were no roads over mountains, nor boats, nor
       bridges over water. All things were produced, each for
       its own proper sphere. Birds and beasts multiplied,
       trees and shrubs grew up. The former might be led by
       the hand; you could climb up and peep into the raven's
       nest. For then man dwelt with birds and beasts, and
       all creation was one. There were no distinctions of good
       and bad men. Being all equally without knowledge,
       their virtue could not go astray. Being all equally
       without evil desires, they were in a state of natural
       integrity, the perfection of human existence.
       But when Sages appeared, tripping up people over
       charity and fettering them with duty to their neighbor,
       doubt found its way into the world. And then, with
       their gushing over music and fussing over ceremony, the
       empire became divided against itself.[11]
       [11] "Musings of a Chinese Mystic." Selections from the Philosophy
       of Chuang Tzu. With an Introduction by Lionel Giles,
       M.A. (Oxon.). Wisdom of the East Series, John Murray, 1911.
       Pages 66-68.
        
       The modern Anarchism, in the sense in which we
       shall be concerned with it, is associated with belief
       in the communal ownership of land and capital, and
       is thus in an important respect akin to Socialism.
       This doctrine is properly called Anarchist Com-
       munism, but as it embraces practically all modern
       Anarchism, we may ignore individualist Anarchism
       altogether and concentrate attention upon the
       communistic form. Socialism and Anarchist Communism
       alike have arisen from the perception that private
       capital is a source of tyranny by certain individuals
       over others. Orthodox Socialism believes that the
       individual will become free if the State becomes the
       sole capitalist. Anarchism, on the contrary, fears
       that in that case the State might merely inherit the
       tyrannical propensities of the private capitalist.
       Accordingly, it seeks for a means of reconciling communal
       ownership with the utmost possible diminution
       in the powers of the State, and indeed ultimately with
       the complete abolition of the State. It has arisen
       mainly within the Socialist movement as its extreme
       left wing.
       In the same sense in which Marx may be regarded
       as the founder of modern Socialism, Bakunin may
       be regarded as the founder of Anarchist Communism.
       But Bakunin did not produce, like Marx, a finished
       and systematic body of doctrine. The nearest
       approach to this will be found in the writings of his
       follower, Kropotkin. In order to explain modern
       Anarchism we shall begin with the life of Bakunin[12]
       and the history of his conflicts with Marx, and shall
       then give a brief account of Anarchist theory as set
       forth partly in his writings, but more in those of
       Kropotkin.[13]
       [12] An account of the life of Bakunin from the Anarchist
       standpoint will be found in vol. ii of the complete edition of
       his works: "Michel Bakounine, OEuvres," Tome II. Avec une
       notice biographique, des avant-propos et des notes, par James
       Guillaume. Paris, P.-V, Stock, editeur, pp. v-lxiii.
       [13] Criticism of these theories will be reserved for Part II.
       Michel Bakunin was born in 1814 of a Russian
       aristocratic family. His father was a diplomatist,
       who at the time of Bakunin's birth had retired to his
       country estate in the Government of Tver. Bakunin
       entered the school of artillery in Petersburg at the
       age of fifteen, and at the age of eighteen was sent as
       an ensign to a regiment stationed in the Government
       of Minsk. The Polish insurrection of 1880 had just
       been crushed. "The spectacle of terrorized Poland,"
       says Guillaume, "acted powerfully on the heart of
       the young officer, and contributed to inspire in him
       the horror of despotism." This led him to give up
       the military career after two years' trial. In 1834
       he resigned his commission and went to Moscow,
       where he spent six years studying philosophy. Like
       all philosophical students of that period, he became
       a Hegelian, and in 1840 he went to Berlin to continue
       his studies, in the hope of ultimately becoming a
       professor. But after this time his opinions underwent
       a rapid change. He found it impossible to
       accept the Hegelian maxim that whatever is, is
       rational, and in 1842 he migrated to Dresden, where
       he became associated with Arnold Ruge, the publisher
       of "Deutsche Jahrbuecher." By this time he had
       become a revolutionary, and in the following year
       he incurred the hostility of the Saxon Government.
       This led him to go to Switzerland, where he came in
       contact with a group of German Communists, but, as
       the Swiss police importuned him and the Russian
       Government demanded his return, he removed to
       Paris, where he remained from 1843 to 1847. These
       years in Paris were important in the formation of his
       outlook and opinions. He became acquainted with
       Proudhon, who exercised a considerable influence on
       him; also with George Sand and many other well-
       known people. It was in Paris that he first made
       the acquaintance of Marx and Engels, with whom he
       was to carry on a lifelong battle. At a much later
       period, in 1871, he gave the following account of his
       relations with Marx at this time:--
       Marx was much more advanced than I was, as he
       remains to-day not more advanced but incomparably more
       learned than I am. I knew then nothing of political
       economy. I had not yet rid myself of metaphysical
       abstractions, and my Socialism was only instinctive. He,
       though younger than I, was already an atheist, an
       instructed materialist, a well-considered Socialist. It
       was just at this time that he elaborated the first foundations
       of his present system. We saw each other fairly
       often, for I respected him much for his learning and his
       passionate and serious devotion (always mixed, however,
       with personal vanity) to the cause of the proletariat,
       and I sought eagerly his conversation, which was always
       instructive and clever, when it was not inspired by a
       paltry hate, which, alas! happened only too often. But
       there was never any frank intimacy between as. Our
       temperaments would not suffer it. He called me a
       sentimental idealist, and he was right; I called him a
       vain man, perfidious and crafty, and I also was right.
       Bakunin never succeeded in staying long in one
       place without incurring the enmity of the authorities.
       In November, 1847, as the result of a speech
       praising the Polish rising of 1830, he was expelled
       from France at the request of the Russian Embassy,
       which, in order to rob him of public sympathy, spread
       the unfounded report that he had been an agent of
       the Russian Government, but was no longer wanted
       because he had gone too far. The French Government,
       by calculated reticence, encouraged this story,
       which clung to him more or less throughout his life.
       Being compelled to leave France, he went to
       Brussels, where he renewed acquaintance with Marx.
       A letter of his, written at this time, shows that he
       entertained already that bitter hatred for which
       afterward he had so much reason. "The Germans,
       artisans, Bornstedt, Marx and Engels--and, above
       all, Marx--are here, doing their ordinary mischief.
       Vanity, spite, gossip, theoretical overbearingness
       and practical pusillanimity--reflections on life, action
       and simplicity, and complete absence of life,
       action and simplicity--literary and argumentative
       artisans and repulsive coquetry with them: `Feuerbach
       is a bourgeois,' and the word `bourgeois' grown
       into an epithet and repeated ad nauseum, but all of
       them themselves from head to foot, through and
       through, provincial bourgeois. With one word, lying
       and stupidity, stupidity and lying. In this society
       there is no possibility of drawing a free, full breath.
       I hold myself aloof from them, and have declared
       quite decidedly that I will not join their communistic
       union of artisans, and will have nothing to do
       with it."
       The Revolution of 1848 led him to return to Paris
       and thence to Germany. He had a quarrel with
       Marx over a matter in which he himself confessed
       later that Marx was in the right. He became a member
       of the Slav Congress in Prague, where he vainly
       endeavored to promote a Slav insurrection. Toward
       the end of 1848, he wrote an "Appeal to Slavs,"
       calling on them to combine with other revolutionaries
       to destroy the three oppressive monarchies, Russia,
       Austria and Prussia. Marx attacked him in print,
       saying, in effect, that the movement for Bohemian
       independence was futile because the Slavs had no
       future, at any rate in those regions where they hap-
       pened to be subject to Germany and Austria.
       Bakunin accused Mars of German patriotism in
       this matter, and Marx accused him of Pan-Slavism,
       no doubt in both cases justly. Before this dispute,
       however, a much more serious quarrel had taken
       place. Marx's paper, the "Neue Rheinische Zeitung,"
       stated that George Sand had papers proving
       Bakunin to be a Russian Government agent and one
       of those responsible for the recent arrest of Poles.
       Bakunin, of course, repudiated the charge, and
       George Sand wrote to the "Neue Rheinische
       Zeitung," denying this statement in toto. The denials
       were published by Marx, and there was a nominal
       reconciliation, but from this time onward there was
       never any real abatement of the hostility between
       these rival leaders, who did not meet again until 1864.
       Meanwhile, the reaction had been everywhere
       gaining ground. In May, 1849, an insurrection in
       Dresden for a moment made the revolutionaries masters
       of the town. They held it for five days and
       established a revolutionary government. Bakunin
       was the soul of the defense which they made against
       the Prussian troops. But they were overpowered,
       and at last Bakunin was captured while trying to
       escape with Heubner and Richard Wagner, the last
       of whom, fortunately for music, was not captured.
       Now began a long period of imprisonment in
       many prisons and various countries. Bakunin was
       sentenced to death on the 14th of January, 1850, but
       his sentence was commuted after five months, and he
       was delivered over to Austria, which claimed the
       privilege of punishing him. The Austrians, in their
       turn, condemned him to death in May, 1851, and
       again his sentence was commuted to imprisonment for
       life. In the Austrian prisons he had fetters on hands
       and feet, and in one of them he was even chained to the
       wall by the belt. There seems to have been some
       peculiar pleasure to be derived from the punishment
       of Bakunin, for the Russian Government in its turn
       demanded him of the Austrians, who delivered him
       up. In Russia he was confined, first in the Peter and
       Paul fortress and then in the Schluesselburg. There
       be suffered from scurvy and all his teeth fell out.
       His health gave way completely, and he found almost
       all food impossible to assimilate. "But, if his body
       became enfeebled, his spirit remained inflexible. He
       feared one thing above all. It was to find himself
       some day led, by the debilitating action of prison,
       to the condition of degradation of which Silvio Pellico
       offers a well-known type. He feared that he might
       cease to hate, that he might feel the sentiment of
       revolt which upheld him becoming extinguished in
       his hearts that he might come to pardon his persecutors
       and resign himself to his fate. But this fear
       was superfluous; his energy did not abandon him a
       single day, and he emerged from his cell the same
       man as when he entered."[14]
       [14] Ibid. p. xxvi.
       After the death of the Tsar Nicholas many political
       prisoners were amnested, but Alexander II with
       his own hand erased Bakunin's name from the list.
       When Bakunin's mother succeeded in obtaining an
       interview with the new Tsar, he said to her, "Know,
       Madame, that so long as your son lives, he can never
       be free." However, in 1857, after eight years of
       captivity, he was sent to the comparative freedom of
       Siberia. From there, in 1861, he succeeded in escaping
       to Japan, and thence through America to London.
       He had been imprisoned for his hostility to
       governments, but, strange to say, his sufferings had
       not had the intended effect of making him love those
       who inflicted them. From this time onward, he
       devoted himself to spreading the spirit of Anarchist
       revolt, without, however, having to suffer any further
       term of imprisonment. For some years he lived in
       Italy, where he founded in 1864 an "International
       Fraternity" or "Alliance of Socialist Revolutionaries."
       This contained men of many countries, but
       apparently no Germans. It devoted itself largely to
       combating Mazzini's nationalism. In 1867 he moved
       to Switzerland, where in the following year he
       helped to found the "International Alliance of So-
       cialist Democracy," of which he drew up the program.
       This program gives a good succinct resume of
       his opinions:--
       The Alliance declares itself atheist; it desires the
       definitive and entire abolition of classes and the political
       equality and social equalization of individuals of both
       sexes. It desires that the earth, the instrument of labor,
       like all other capital, becoming the collective property of
       society as a whole, shall be no longer able to be utilized
       except by the workers, that is to say, by agricultural and
       industrial associations. It recognizes that all actually
       existing political and authoritarian States, reducing
       themselves more and more to the mere administrative functions
       of the public services in their respective countries,
       must disappear in the universal union of free
       associations, both agricultural and industrial.
       The International Alliance of Socialist Democracy
       desired to become a branch of the International
       Working Men's Association, but was refused admission
       on the ground that branches must be local, and
       could not themselves be international. The Geneva
       group of the Alliance, however, was admitted later,
       in July, 1869.
       The International Working Men's Association
       had been founded in London in 1864, and its statutes
       and program were drawn up by Marx. Bakunin at
       first did not expect it to prove a success and refused
       to join it. But it spread with remarkable rapidity
       in many countries and soon became a great power
       for the propagation of Socialist ideas. Originally
       it was by no means wholly Socialist, but in successive
       Congresses Marx won it over more and more to his
       views. At its third Congress, in Brussels in September,
       1868, it became definitely Socialist. Meanwhile
       Bakunin, regretting his earlier abstention, had
       decided to join it, and he brought with him a
       considerable following in French-Switzerland, France,
       Spain and Italy. At the fourth Congress, held at
       Basle in September, 1869, two currents were strongly
       marked. The Germans and English followed Marx
       in his belief in the State as it was to become after the
       abolition of private property; they followed him also
       in his desire to found Labor Parties in the various
       countries, and to utilize the machinery of democracy
       for the election oœ representatives of Labor to
       Parliaments. On the other hand, the Latin nations in
       the main followed Bakunin in opposing the State and
       disbelieving in the machinery of representative
       government. The conflict between these two groups grew
       more and more bitter, and each accused the other
       of various offenses. The statement that Bakunin
       was a spy was repeated, but was withdrawn after
       investigation. Marx wrote in a confidential
       communication to his German friends that Bakunin was
       an agent of the Pan-Slavist party and received from
       them 25,000 francs a year. Meanwhile, Bakunin
       became for a time interested in the attempt to stir
       up an agrarian revolt in Russia, and this led him
       to neglect the contest in the International at a crucial
       moment. During the Franco-Prussian war Bakunin
       passionately took the side of France, especially after
       the fall of Napoleon III. He endeavored to rouse
       the people to revolutionary resistance like that of
       1793, and became involved in an abortive attempt at
       revolt in Lyons. The French Government accused
       him of being a paid agent of Prussia, and it was
       with difficulty that he escaped to Switzerland. The
       dispute with Marx and his followers had become
       exacerbated by the national dispute. Bakunin, like
       Kropotkin after him, regarded the new power of
       Germany as the greatest menace to liberty in the
       world. He hated the Germans with a bitter hatred,
       partly, no doubt, on account of Bismarck, but probably
       still more on account of Marx. To this day,
       Anarchism has remained confined almost exclusively
       to the Latin countries, and has been associated with, a
       hatred of Germany, growing out of the contests
       between Marx and Bakunin in the International.
       The final suppression of Bakunin's faction
       occurred at the General Congress of the International
       at the Hague in 1872. The meeting-place was
       chosen by the General Council (in which Marx was
       unopposed), with a view--so Bakunin's friends contend--
       to making access impossible for Bakunin (on
       account of the hostility of the French and German
       governments) and difficult for his friends. Bakunin
       was expelled from the International as the result of
       a report accusing him inter alia of theft backed; up
       by intimidation.
       The orthodoxy of the International was saved,
       but at the cost of its vitality. From this time onward,
       it ceased to be itself a power, but both sections continued
       to work in their various groups, and the Socialist
       groups in particular grew rapidly. Ultimately
       a new International was formed (1889) which continued
       down to the outbreak of the present war. As
       to the future of International Socialism it would be
       rash to prophesy, though it would seem that the
       international idea has acquired sufficient strength to
       need again, after the war, some such means of expression
       as it found before in Socialist congresses.
       By this time Bakunin's health was broken, and
       except for a few brief intervals, he lived in retirement
       until his death in 1876.
       Bakunin's life, unlike Marx's, was a very stormy
       one. Every kind of rebellion against authority
       always aroused his sympathy, and in his support he
       never paid the slightest attention to personal risk.
       His influence, undoubtedly very great, arose chiefly
       through the influence of his personality upon important
       individuals. His writings differ from Marx's as
       much as his life does, and in a similar way. They are
       chaotic, largely, aroused by some passing occasion,
       abstract and metaphysical, except when they deal
       with current politics. He does not come to close
       quarters with economic facts, but dwells usually in
       the regions of theory and metaphysics. When he
       descends from these regions, he is much more at the
       mercy of current international politics than Marx,
       much less imbued with the consequences of the belief
       that it is economic causes that are fundamental. He
       praised Marx for enunciating this doctrine,[15] but
       nevertheless continued to think in terms of nations.
       His longest work, "L'Empire Knouto-Germanique et
       la Revolution Sociale," is mainly concerned with the
       situation in France during the later stages of the
       Franco-Prussian War, and with the means of resisting
       German imperialism. Most of his writing was
       done in a hurry in the interval between two insurrections.
       There is something of Anarchism in his lack
       of literary order. His best-known work is a fragment
       entitled by its editors "God and the State."[16]
       In this work he represents belief in God and belief in
       the State as the two great obstacles to human liberty.
       A typical passage will serve to illustrate its style.
       [15] "Marx, as a thinker, is on the right road. He has established
       as a principle that all the evolutions, political, religious,
       and juridical, in history are, not the causes, but the effects of
       economic evolutions. This is a great and fruitful thought, which
       he has not absolutely invented; it has been glimpsed, expressed
       in part, by many others besides him; but in any case to him
       belongs the honor of having solidly established it and of having
       enunciated it as the basis of his whole economic system. (1870;
       ib. ii. p. xiii.)
       [16] This title is not Bakunin's, but was invented by Cafiero
       and Elisee Reclus, who edited it, not knowing that it was a
       fragment of what was intended to he the second version of
       "L'Empire Knouto-Germanique" (see ib. ii. p 283).
        
       The State is not society, it is only an historical form
       of it, as brutal as it is abstract. It was born historically
       in all countries of the marriage of violence, rapine, pillage,
       in a word, war and conquest, with the gods successively
       created by the theological fantasy of nations.
       It has been from its origin, and it remains still at present,
       the divine sanction of brutal force and triumphant
       inequality.
       The State is authority; it is force; it is the ostentation
       and infatuation of force: it does not insinuate
       itself; it does not seek to convert. . . . Even when
       it commands what is good, it hinders and spoils it, just
       because it commands it, and because every command provokes
       and excites the legitimate revolts of liberty; and
       because the good, from the moment that it is commanded,
       becomes evil from the point of view of true morality, of
       human morality (doubtless not of divine), from the point
       of view of human respect and of liberty. Liberty, morality,
       and the human dignity of man consist precisely
       in this, that he does good, not because it is commanded,
       but because he conceives it, wills it and loves it.
       We do not find in Bakunin's works a clear picture
       of the society at which he aimed, or any argument
       to prove that such a society could be stable.
       If we wish to understand Anarchism we must turn
       to his followers, and especially to Kropotkin--like
       him, a Russian aristocrat familiar with the prisons
       of Europe, and, like him, an Anarchist who, in spite
       of his internationalism, is imbued with a fiery hatred
       of the Germans.
       Kropotkin has devoted much of his writing to
       technical questions of production. In "Fields,
       Factories and Workshops" and "The Conquest of
       Bread" he has set himself to prove that, if production
       were more scientific and better organized, a
       comparatively small amount of quite agreeable work
       would suffice to keep the whole population in comfort.
       Even assuming, as we probably must, that he
       somewhat exaggerates what is possible with our
       present scientific knowledge, it must nevertheless be
       conceded that his contentions contain a very large
       measure of truth. In attacking the subject of production
       he has shown that he knows what is the really
       crucial question. If civilization and progress are to
       be compatible with equality, it is necessary that
       equality should not involve long hours of painful
       toil for little more than the necessaries of life, since,
       where there is no leisure, art and science will die and
       all progress will become impossible. The objection
       which some feel to Socialism and Anarchism alike on
       this ground cannot be upheld in view of the possible
       productivity of labor.
       The system at which Kropotkin aims, whether or
       not it be possible, is certainly one which demands a
       very great improvement in the methods of production
       above what is common at present. He desires
       to abolish wholly the system of wages, not only, as
       most Socialists do, in the sense that a man is to be
       paid rather for his willingness to work than for the
       actual work demanded of him, but in a more fundamental
       sense: there is to be no obligation to work,
       and all things are to be shared in equal proportions
       among the whole population. Kropotkin relies upon
       the possibility of making work pleasant: he holds
       that, in such a community as he foresees, practically
       everyone will prefer work to idleness, because work will
       not involve overwork or slavery, or that excessive
       specialization that industrialism has brought about,
       but will be merely a pleasant activity for certain
       hours of the day, giving a man an outlet for his
       spontaneous constructive impulses. There is to be no
       compulsion, no law, no government exercising force;
       there will still be acts of the community, but these
       are to spring from universal consent, not from any
       enforced submission of even the smallest minority.
       We shall examine in a later chapter how far such
       an ideal is realizable, but it cannot be denied that
       Kropotkin presents it with extraordinary persuasiveness
       and charm.
       We should be doing more than justice to Anarchism
       if we did not say something of its darker side,
       the side which has brought it into conflict with the
       police and made it a word of terror to ordinary citizens.
       In its general doctrines there is nothing essentially
       involving violent methods or a virulent hatred
       of the rich, and many who adopt these general doctrines
       are personally gentle and temperamentally
       averse from violence. But the general tone of the
       Anarchist press and public is bitter to a degree that
       seems scarcely sane, and the appeal, especially in
       Latin countries, is rather to envy of the fortunate
       than to pity for the unfortunate. A vivid and readable,
       though not wholly reliable, account, from a
       hostile point of view, is given in a book called "Le
       Peril Anarchiste," by Felix Dubois,[17] which
       incidentally reproduces a number of cartoons from anarchist
       journals. The revolt against law naturally leads,
       except in those who are controlled by a real passion
       for humanity, to a relaxation of all the usually
       accepted moral rules, and to a bitter spirit of
       retaliatory cruelty out of which good can hardly come.
       [17] Paris, 1894.
       One of the most curious features of popular
       Anarchism is its martyrology, aping Christian forms,
       with the guillotine (in France) in place of the cross.
       Many who have suffered death at the hands of the
       authorities on account of acts of violence were no
       doubt genuine sufferers for their belief in a cause,
       but others, equally honored, are more questionable.
       One of the most curious examples of this outlet for
       the repressed religious impulse is the cult of Ravachol,
       who was guillotined in 1892 on account of
       various dynamite outrages. His past was dubious,
       but he died defiantly; his last words were three lines
       from a well-known Anarchist song, the "Chant du
       Pere Duchesne":--
       Si tu veux etre heureux,
       Nom de Dieu!
       Pends ton proprietaire.
       As was natural, the leading Anarchists took no part
       in the canonization of his memory; nevertheless it
       proceeded, with the most amazing extravagances.
       It would be wholly unfair to judge Anarchist
       doctrine, or the views of its leading exponents, by
       such phenomena; but it remains a fact that Anarchism
       attracts to itself much that lies on the borderland
       of insanity and common crime.[18] This must be
       remembered in exculpation of the authorities and
       the thoughtless public, who often confound in a common
       detestation the parasites of the movement and
       the truly heroic and high-minded men who have elaborated
       its theories and sacrificed comfort and success
       to their propagation.
       [18] The attitude of all the better Anarchists is that expressed
       by L. S. Bevington in the words: "Of course we know that
       among those who call themselves Anarchists there are a minority
       of unbalanced enthusiasts who look upon every illegal and sensational
       act of violence as a matter for hysterical jubilation.
       Very useful to the police and the press, unsteady in intellect
       and of weak moral principle, they have repeatedly shown themselves
       accessible to venal considerations. They, and their violence,
       and their professed Anarchism are purchasable, and in
       the last resort they are welcome and efficient partisans of the
       bourgeoisie in its remorseless war against the deliverers of the
       people." His conclusion is a very wise one: "Let us leave
       indiscriminate killing and injuring to the Government--to its
       Statesmen, its Stockbrokers, its Officers, and its Law." ("Anarchism
       and Violence," pp. 9-10. Liberty Press, Chiswick, 1896.)
       The terrorist campaign in which such men as
       Ravachol were active practically came to an end in
       1894. After that time, under the influence of Pelloutier,
       the better sort of Anarchists found a less
       harmful outlet by advocating Revolutionary Syndicalism
       in the Trade Unions and Bourses du Travail.[19]
       [19] See next Chapter.
       The ECONOMIC organization of society, as conceived
       by Anarchist Communists, does not differ
       greatly from that which is sought by Socialists.
       Their difference from Socialists is in the matter of
       government: they demand that government shall
       require the consent of all the governed, and not only
       of a majority. It is undeniable that the rule of a
       majority may be almost as hostile to freedom as the
       rule of a minority: the divine right of majorities is a
       dogma as little possessed of absolute truth as any
       other. A strong democratic State may easily be led
       into oppression of its best citizens, namely, those
       those independence of mind would make them a force
       for progress. Experience of democratic parliamentary
       government has shown that it falls very far
       short of what was expected of it by early Socialists,
       and the Anarchist revolt against it is not surprising.
       But in the form of pure Anarchism, this revolt has
       remained weak and sporadic. It is Syndicalism, and
       the movements to which Syndicalism has given rise,
       that have popularized the revolt against parliamentary
       government and purely political means of emancipating
       the wage earner. But this movement must
       be dealt with in a separate chapter.
       _____
       Content of PART I - HISTORICAL. CHAPTER II - BAKUNIN AND ANARCHISM [Bertrand Russell's book: Proposed Roads To Freedom] _