您的位置 : 首页 > 英文著作
Proposed Roads To Freedom
PART I - HISTORICAL   PART I - HISTORICAL - CHAPTER I - MARX AND SOCIALIST DOCTRINE
Bertrand Russell
下载:Proposed Roads To Freedom.txt
本书全文检索:
       _ PART I-HISTORICAL. CHAPTER I - MARX AND SOCIALIST DOCTRINE
       SOCIALISM, like everything else that is vital, is
       rather a tendency than a strictly definable body of
       doctrine. A definition of Socialism is sure either to
       include some views which many would regard as not
       Socialistic, or to exclude others which claim to be
       included. But I think we shall come nearest to the
       essence of Socialism by defining it as the advocacy
       of communal ownership of land and capital. Communal
       ownership may mean ownership by a democratic
       State, but cannot be held to include ownership
       by any State which is not democratic. Communal
       ownership may also be understood, as Anarchist
       Communism understands it, in the sense of
       ownership by the free association of the men and
       women in a community without those compulsory
       powers which are necessary to constitute a State.
       Some Socialists expect communal ownership to arrive
       suddenly and completely by a catastrophic revolution,
       while others expect it to come gradually, first
       in one industry, then in another. Some insist upon
       the necessity of completeness in the acquisition of
       land and capital by the public, while others would
       be content to see lingering islands of private ownership,
       provided they were not too extensive or powerful.
       What all forms have in common is democracy
       and the abolition, virtual or complete, of the present
       capitalistic system. The distinction between Socialists,
       Anarchists and Syndicalists turns largely upon
       the kind of democracy which they desire. Orthodox
       Socialists are content with parliamentary democracy
       in the sphere of government, holding that the evils
       apparent in this form of constitution at present
       would disappear with the disappearance of capitalism.
       Anarchists and Syndicalists, on the other
       hand, object to the whole parliamentary machinery,
       and aim at a different method of regulating the political
       affairs of the community. But all alike are
       democratic in the sense that they aim at abolishing
       every kind of privilege and every kind of artificial
       inequality: all alike are champions of the wage-
       earner in existing society. All three also have much
       in common in their economic doctrine. All three
       regard capital and the wages system as a means of
       exploiting the laborer in the interests of the possessing
       classes, and hold that communal ownership, in one
       form or another, is the only means of bringing freedom
       to the producers. But within the framework
       of this common doctrine there are many divergences,
       and even among those who are strictly to be called
       Socialists, there is a very considerable diversity of
       schools.
       Socialism as a power in Europe may be said
       to begin with Marx. It is true that before his time
       there were Socialist theories, both in England and in
       France. It is also true that in France, during the
       revolution of 1848, Socialism for a brief period
       acquired considerable influence in the State. But
       the Socialists who preceded Marx tended to indulge
       in Utopian dreams and failed to found any strong or
       stable political party. To Marx, in collaboration
       with Engels, are due both the formulation of a coherent
       body of Socialist doctrine, sufficiently true or
       plausible to dominate the minds of vast numbers of
       men, and the formation of the International Socialist
       movement, which has continued to grow in all
       European countries throughout the last fifty years.
       In order to understand Marx's doctrine, it is
       necessary to know something of the influences which
       formed his outlook. He was born in 1818 at Treves
       in the Rhine Provinces, his father being a legal
       official, a Jew who had nominally accepted
       Christianity. Marx studied jurisprudence, philosophy,
       political economy and history at various German
       universities. In philosophy he imbibed the doctrines
       of Hegel, who was then at the height of his fame,
       and something of these doctrines dominated his
       thought throughout his life. Like Hegel, he saw in
       history the development of an Idea. He conceived
       the changes in the world as forming a logical development,
       in which one phase passes by revolution into
       another, which is its antithesis--a conception which
       gave to his views a certain hard abstractness, and a
       belief in revolution rather than evolution. But of
       Hegel's more definite doctrines Marx retained nothing
       after his youth. He was recognized as a brilliant
       student, and might have had a prosperous career as
       a professor or an official, but his interest in politics
       and his Radical views led him into more arduous
       paths. Already in 1842 he became editor of a newspaper,
       which was suppressed by the Prussian Government
       early in the following year on account of
       its advanced opinions. This led Marx to go to Paris,
       where he became known as a Socialist and acquired
       a knowledge of his French predecessors.[1] Here in the
       year 1844 began his lifelong friendship with Engels,
       who had been hitherto in business in Manchester,
       where he had become acquainted with English Socialism
       and had in the main adopted its doctrines.[2] In
       1845 Marx was expelled from Paris and went with
       Engels to live in Brussels. There he formed a German
       Working Men's Association and edited a paper
       which was their organ. Through his activities in
       Brussels he became known to the German Communist
       League in Paris, who, at the end of 1847, invited him
       and Engels to draw up for them a manifesto, which
       appeared in January, 1848. This is the famous
       "Communist Manifesto," in which for the first time
       Marx's system is set forth. It appeared at a fortunate
       moment. In the following month, February,
       the revolution broke out in Paris, and in March it
       spread to Germany. Fear of the revolution led the
       Brussels Government to expel Marx from Belgium,
       but the German revolution made it possible for him
       to return to his own country. In Germany he again
       edited a paper, which again led him into a conflict
       with the authorities, increasing in severity as the
       reaction gathered force. In June, 1849, his paper
       was suppressed, and he was expelled from Prussia.
       He returned to Paris, but was expelled from there
       also. This led him to settle in England--at that
       time an asylum for friends of freedom--and in England,
       with only brief intervals for purposes of agitation,
       he continued to live until his death in 1883.
       [1] Chief among these were Fourier and Saint-Simon, who
       constructed somewhat fantastic Socialistic ideal commonwealths.
       Proudhon, with whom Marx had some not wholly friendly relations,
       is to be regarded as a forerunner of the Anarchists rather
       than of orthodox Socialism.
       [2] Marx mentions the English Socialists with praise in "The
       Poverty of Philosophy" (1847). They, like him, tend to base
       their arguments upon a Ricardian theory of value, but they
       have not his scope or erudition or scientific breadth. Among
       them may be mentioned Thomas Hodgskin (1787-1869), originally
       an officer in the Navy, but dismissed for a pamphlet critical
       of the methods of naval discipline, author of "Labour Defended
       Against the Claims of Capital" (1825) and other works;
       William Thompson (1785-1833), author of "Inquiry into the
       Principles of Distribution of Wealth Most Conducive to Human
       Happiness" (1824), and "Labour Rewarded" (1825); and
       Piercy Ravenstone, from whom Hodgskin's ideas are largely
       derived. Perhaps more important than any of these was Robert
       Owen.
       The bulk of his time was occupied in the composition
       of his great book, "Capital."[3] His other
       important work during his later years was the formation
       and spread of the International Working Men's
       Association. From 1849 onward the greater part
       of his time was spent in the British Museum, accumulating,
       with German patience, the materials for his
       terrific indictment of capitalist society, but he
       retained his hold on the International Socialist movement.
       In several countries he had sons-in-law as
       lieutenants, like Napoleon's brothers, and in the
       various internal contests that arose his will generally
       prevailed.
       [3] The first and most important volume appeared in 1867;
       the other two volumes were published posthumously (1885 and
       1894).
       The most essential of Marx's doctrines may be
       reduced to three: first, what is called the material-
       istic interpretation of history; second, the law of the
       concentration of capital; and, third, the class-war.
       1. The Materialistic Interpretation of History.--
       Marx holds that in the main all the phenomena of
       human society have their origin in material conditions,
       and these he takes to be embodied in economic
       systems. Political constitutions, laws, religions,
       philosophies--all these he regards as, in their broad
       outlines, expressions of the economic regime in the
       society that gives rise to them. It would be unfair
       to represent him as maintaining that the conscious
       economic motive is the only one of importance; it
       is rather that economics molds character and opinion,
       and is thus the prime source of much that appears
       in consciousness to have no connection with them.
       He applies his doctrine in particular to two revolutions,
       one in the past, the other in the future. The
       revolution in the past is that of the bourgeoisie
       against feudalism, which finds its expression, according
       to him, particularly in the French Revolution.
       The one in the future is the revolution of the wage-
       earners, or proletariat, against the bourgeoisie,
       which is to establish the Socialist Commonwealth.
       The whole movement of history is viewed by him as
       necessary, as the effect of material causes operating
       upon human beings. He does not so much advocate
       the Socialist revolution as predict it. He holds, it
       is true, that it will be beneficent, but he is much more
       concerned to prove that it must inevitably come.
       The same sense of necessity is visible in his exposition
       of the evils of the capitalist system. He does
       not blame capitalists for the cruelties of which he
       shows them to have been guilty; he merely points out
       that they are under an inherent necessity to behave
       cruelly so long as private ownership of land and
       capital continues. But their tyranny will not last
       forever, for it generates the forces that must in the
       end overthrow it.
       2. The Law of the Concentration of Capital.--
       Marx pointed out that capitalist undertakings tend
       to grow larger and larger. He foresaw the substitution
       of trusts for free competition, and predicted
       that the number of capitalist enterprises must diminish
       as the magnitude of single enterprises increased.
       He supposed that this process must involve a diminution,
       not only in the number of businesses, but also
       in the number of capitalists. Indeed, he usually
       spoke as though each business were owned by a single
       man. Accordingly, he expected that men would be
       continually driven from the ranks of the capitalists
       into those of the proletariat, and that the capitalists,
       in the course of time, would grow numerically weaker
       and weaker. He applied this principle not only to
       industry but also to agriculture. He expected to
       find the landowners growing fewer and fewer while
       their estates grew larger and larger. This process
       was to make more and more glaring the evils and
       injustices of the capitalist system, and to stimulate
       more and more the forces of opposition.
       3. The Class War.--Marx conceives the wage-
       earner and the capitalist in a sharp antithesis. He
       imagines that every man is, or must soon become,
       wholly the one or wholly the other. The wage-
       earner, who possesses nothing, is exploited by the
       capitalists, who possess everything. As the capitalist
       system works itself out and its nature becomes more
       clear, the opposition of bourgeoisie and proletariat
       becomes more and more marked. The two classes,
       since they have antagonistic interests, are forced
       into a class war which generates within the capitalist
       regime internal forces of disruption. The working
       men learn gradually to combine against their
       exploiters, first locally, then nationally, and at last
       internationally. When they have learned to combine
       internationally they must be victorious. They
       will then decree that all land and capital shall be
       owned in common; exploitation will cease; the tyranny
       of the owners of wealth will no longer be
       possible; there will no longer be any division of
       society into classes, and all men will be free.
       All these ideas are already contained in the
       "Communist Manifesto," a work of the most amazing
       vigor and force, setting forth with terse compression
       the titanic forces of the world, their epic battle, and
       the inevitable consummation. This work is of such
       importance in the development of Socialism and
       gives such an admirable statement of the doctrines
       set forth at greater length and with more pedantry
       in "Capital," that its salient passages must be
       known by anyone who wishes to understand the hold
       which Marxian Socialism has acquired over the intellect
       and imagination of a large proportion of working-class
       leaders.
       "A spectre is haunting Europe," it begins, "the
       spectre of Communism. All the Powers of old
       Europe have entered into a holy alliance to exorcise
       this spectre--Pope and Czar, Metternich and Guizot,
       French Radicals and German police-spies. Where
       is the party in opposition that has not been decried
       as communistic by its opponents in power? Where
       the Opposition that has not hurled back the branding
       reproach of Communism against the more
       advanced opposition parties, as well as against its
       re-actionary adversaries?"
       The existence of a class war is nothing new:
       "The history of all hitherto existing society is the
       history of class struggles." In these struggles the
       fight "each time ended, either in a revolutionary
       re-constitution of society at large, or in the common
       ruin of the contending classes."
       "Our epoch, the epoch of the bourgeoisie . . .
       has simplified the class antagonisms. Society as a
       whole is more and more splitting up into two great
       hostile camps, into two great classes directly facing
       each other: Bourgeoisie and Proletariat." Then follows
       a history of the fall of feudalism, leading to a
       description of the bourgeoisie as a revolutionary
       force. "The bourgeoisie, historically, has played a
       most revolutionary part." "For exploitation, veiled
       by religious and political illusions, it has substituted
       naked, shameless, direct, brutal exploitation." "The
       need of a constantly expanding market for its products
       chases the bourgeoisie over the whole surface
       of the globe." "The bourgeoisie, during its rule of
       scarce one hundred years, has created more massive
       and more colossal productive forces than have all
       preceding generations together." Feudal relations
       became fetters: "They had to be burst asunder;
       they were burst asunder. . . . A similar movement
       is going on before our own eyes." "The weapons
       with which the bourgeoisie felled feudalism to the
       ground are now turned against the bourgeoisie itself.
       But not only has the bourgoisie forged the weapons
       that bring death to itself; it has also called into
       existence the men who are to wield those weapons--
       the modern working class--the proletarians."
       The cause of the destitution of the proletariat
       are then set forth. "The cost of production of a
       workman is restricted, almost entirely, to the means
       of subsistence that he requires for his maintenance
       and for the propagation of his race. But the price
       of a commodity, and therefore also of labor, is equal
       to its cost of production. In proportion, therefore,
       as the repulsiveness of the work increases, the wage
       decreases. Nay more, in proportion as the use of
       machinery and diversion of labor increases, in the
       same proportion the burden of toil also increases."
       "Modern industry has converted the little workshop
       of the patriarchal master into the great factory
       of the industrial capitalist. Masses of laborers,
       crowded into the factory, are organized like soldiers.
       As privates of the industrial army they are placed
       under the command of a perfect hierarchy of officers
       and sergeants. Not only are they slaves of the bourgeois
       class, and of the bourgeois State, they are
       daily and hourly enslaved by the machine, by the
       over-looker, and, above all, by the individual
       bourgeois manufacturer himself. The more openly this
       despotism proclaims gain to be its end and aim, the
       more petty, the more hateful, and the more embittering
       it is."
       The Manifesto tells next the manner of growth
       of the class struggle. "The proletariat goes
       through various stages of development. With its
       birth begins its struggle with the bourgeoisie. At
       first the contest is carried on by individual laborers,
       then by the workpeople of a factory, then by the
       operatives of one trade, in one locality, against the
       individual bourgeois who directly exploits them.
       They direct their attacks not against the bourgeois
       conditions of production, but against the instruments
       of production themselves."
       "At this stage the laborers still form an incoherent
       mass scattered over the whole country, and broken
       up by their mutual competition. If anywhere they
       unite to form more compact bodies, this is not yet
       the consequence of their own active union, but of
       the union of the bourgeoisie, which class, in order to
       attain its own political ends, is compelled to set the
       whole proletariat in motion, and is moreover yet, for
       a time, able to do so."
       "The collisions between individual workmen and
       individual bourgeois take more and more the character
       of collisions between two classes. Thereupon
       the workers begin to form combinations (Trades
       Unions) against the bourgeois; they club together
       in order to keep up the rate of wages; they found
       permanent associations in order to make provision
       beforehand for these occasional revolts. Here and
       there the contest breaks out into riots. Now and
       then the workers are victorious, but only for a time.
       The real fruit of their battles lies, not in the immediate
       result, but in the ever-expanding union of
       the workers. This union is helped on by the im-
       proved means of communication that are created
       by modern industry, and that place the workers
       of different localities in contact with one another.
       It was just this contact that was needed to centralize
       the numerous local struggles, all of the same character,
       into one national struggle between classes.
       But every class struggle is a political struggle. And
       that union, to attain which the burghers of the
       Middle Ages, with their miserable highways, required
       centuries, the modern proletarians, thanks to railways,
       achieve in a few years. This organization of
       the proletarians into a class, and consequently into
       a political party, is continually being upset again by
       the competition between the workers themselves. But
       it ever rises up again, stronger, firmer, mightier. It
       compels legislative recognition of particular interests
       of the workers, by taking advantage of the divisions
       among the bourgeoisie itself."
       "In the conditions of the proletariat, those of
       old society at large are already virtually swamped.
       The proletarian is without property; his relation
       to his wife and children has no longer anything in
       common with the bourgeois family-relations; modern
       industrial labor, modern subjection to capital, the
       same in England as in France, in America as in
       Germany, has stripped him of every trace of national
       character. Law, morality, religion, are to him so
       many bourgeois prejudices, behind which lurk in
       ambush just as many bourgeois interests. All the
       preceding classes that got the upper hand, sought
       to fortify their already acquired status by subjecting
       society at large to their conditions of appropriation.
       The proletarians cannot become masters
       of the productive forces of society, except by abolishing
       their own previous mode of appropriation, and
       thereby also every other previous mode of appropriation.
       They have nothing of their own to secure and to
       fortify; their mission is to destroy all previous
       securities for, and insurances of, individual property.
       All previous historical movements were movements
       of minorities, or in the interest of minorities. The
       proletarian movement is the self-conscious, independent
       movement of the immense majority, in the
       interest of the immense majority. The proletariat,
       the lowest stratum of our present society, cannot
       stir, cannot raise itself up, without the whole super-
       incumbent strata of official society being sprung
       into the air."
       The Communists, says Marx, stand for the proletariat
       as a whole. They are international. "The
       Communists are further reproached with desiring
       to abolish countries and nationality. The working
       men have no country. We cannot take from them
       what they have not got."
       The immediate aim of the Communists is the conquests
       of political power by the proletariat. "The
       theory of the Communists may be summed up in the
       single sentence: Abolition of private property."
       The materialistic interpretation of history is
       used to answer such charges as that Communism is
       anti-Christian. "The charges against Communism
       made from a religious, a philosophical, and, generally,
       from an ideological standpoint, are not deserving
       of serious examination. Does it require deep
       intuition to comprehend that man's ideas, views and
       conceptions, in one word, man's consciousness,
       changes with every change in the conditions of his
       material existence, in his social relations, and in his
       social life?"
       The attitude of the Manifesto to the State is not
       altogether easy to grasp. "The executive of the
       modern State," we are told, "is but a Committee for
       managing the common affairs of the whole bourgeoisie."
       Nevertheless, the first step for the proletariat
       must be to acquire control of the State. "We have
       seen above, that the first step in the revolution by the
       working class, is to raise the proletariat to the position
       of ruling class, to win the battle of democracy.
       The proletariat will use its political supremacy to
       wrest, by degrees, all capital from the bourgeoisie,
       to centralize all instruments of production in the
       hands of the State, i.e., of the proletariat organized
       as the ruling class; and to increase the total of productive
       forces as rapidly as possible."
       The Manifesto passes on to an immediate program
       of reforms, which would in the first instance
       much increase the power of the existing State, but
       it is contended that when the Socialist revolution is
       accomplished, the State, as we know it, will have
       ceased to exist. As Engels says elsewhere, when the
       proletariat seizes the power of the State "it puts an
       end to all differences of class and antagonisms of
       class, and consequently also puts an end to the State
       as a State." Thus, although State Socialism might,
       in fact, be the outcome of the proposals of Marx and
       Engels, they cannot themselves be accused of any
       glorification of the State.
       The Manifesto ends with an appeal to the wage-
       earners of the world to rise on behalf of Communism.
       "The Communists disdain to conceal their views and
       aims. They openly declare that their ends can be
       attained only by the forcible overthrow of all existing
       social conditions. Let the ruling classes tremble
       at a Communistic revolution. The proletarians have
       nothing to lose but their chains. They have a world
       to win. Working men of all countries, unite!"
       In all the great countries of the Continent,
       except Russia, a revolution followed quickly on the
       publication of the Communist Manifesto, but the
       revolution was not economic or international, except
       at first in France. Everywhere else it was inspired
       by the ideas of nationalism. Accordingly, the rulers
       of the world, momentarily terrified, were able to
       recover power by fomenting the enmities inherent
       in the nationalist idea, and everywhere, after a very
       brief triumph, the revolution ended in war and
       reaction. The ideas of the Communist Manifesto
       appeared before the world was ready for them, but
       its authors lived to see the beginnings of the growth
       of that Socialist movement in every country, which
       has pressed on with increasing force, influencing
       Governments more and more, dominating the Russian
       Revolution, and perhaps capable of achieving
       at no very distant date that international triumph to
       which the last sentences of the Manifesto summon
       the wage-earners of the world.
       Marx's magnum opus, "Capital," added bulk
       and substance to the theses of the Communist Manifesto.
       It contributed the theory of surplus value,
       which professed to explain the actual mechanism
       of capitalist exploitation. This doctrine is very
       complicated and is scarcely tenable as a contribution
       to pure theory. It is rather to be viewed as a translation
       into abstract terms of the hatred with which
       Marx regarded the system that coins wealth out of
       human lives, and it is in this spirit, rather than in
       that of disinterested analysis, that it has been read
       by its admirers. A critical examination of the theory
       of surplus value would require much difficult and
       abstract discussion of pure economic theory without
       having much bearing upon the practical truth or
       falsehood of Socialism; it has therefore seemed impossible
       within the limits of the present volume. To
       my mind the best parts of the book are those which
       deal with economic facts, of which Marx's knowledge
       was encyclopaedic. It was by these facts that
       he hoped to instil into his disciples that firm and
       undying hatred that should make them soldiers to
       the death in the class war. The facts which he
       accumulates are such as are practically unknown to
       the vast majority of those who live comfortable lives.
       They are very terrible facts, and the economic system
       which generates them must be acknowledged to be
       a very terrible system. A few examples of his choice
       of facts will serve to explain the bitterness of many
       Socialists:--
       Mr. Broughton Charlton, county magistrate, declared,
       as chairman of a meeting held at the Assembly Rooms,
       Nottingham, on the 14th January, 1860, "that there was
       an amount of privation and suffering among that portion
       of the population connected with the lace trade, unknown
       in other parts of the kingdom, indeed, in the civilized
       world. . . . Children of nine or ten years are dragged
       from their squalid beds at two, three, or four o clock in
       the morning and compelled to work for a bare subsistence
       until ten, eleven, or twelve at night, their limbs wearing
       away, their frames dwindling, their faces whitening,
       and their humanity absolutely sinking into a stone-like
       torpor, utterly horrible to contemplate."[4]
       [4] Vol. i, p. 227.
       Three railway men are standing before a London coroner's
       jury--a guard, an engine-driver, a signalman.
       A tremendous railway accident has hurried hundreds of
       passengers into another world. The negligence of the
       employes is the cause of the misfortune. They declare
       with one voice before the jury that ten or twelve years
       before, their labor only lasted eight hours a day. During
       the last five or six years it had been screwed up to
       14, 18, and 20 hours, and under a specially severe pressure
       of holiday-makers, at times of excursion trains, it
       often lasted 40 or 50 hours without a break. They
       were ordinary men, not Cyclops. At a certain point their
       labor-power failed. Torpor seized them. Their brain
       ceased to think, their eyes to see. The thoroughly
       "respectable" British jurymen answered by a verdict that
       sent them to the next assizes on a charge of manslaughter,
       and, in a gentle "rider" to their verdict, expressed the
       pious hope that the capitalistic magnates of the railways
       would, in future, be more extravagant in the purchase of
       a sufficient quantity of labor-power, and more "abstemious,"
       more "self-denying," more "thrifty," in the
       draining of paid labor-power.[5]
       [5] Vol. i, pp. 237, 238.
       In the last week of June, 1863, all the London daily
       papers published a paragraph with the "sensational"
       heading, "Death from simple over-work." It dealt with
       the death of the milliner, Mary Anne Walkley, 20 years
       of age, employed in a highly respectable dressmaking
       establishment, exploited by a lady with the pleasant name
       of Elise. The old, often-told story was once more recounted.
       This girl worked, on an average, 16 1/2 hours,
       during the season often 30 hours, without a break, whilst
       her failing labor-power was revived by occasional supplies
       of sherry, port, or coffee. It was just now the
       height of the season. It was necessary to conjure up
       in the twinkling of an eye the gorgeous dresses for the
       noble ladies bidden to the ball in honor of the newly-
       imported Princess of Wales. Mary Anne Walkley had
       worked without intermission for 26 1/2 hours, with 60
       other girls, 30 in one room, that only afforded 1/3 of
       the cubic feet of air required for them. At night, they
       slept in pairs in one of the stifling holes into which the
       bedroom was divided by partitions of board. And this
       was one of the best millinery establishments in London.
       Mary Anne Walkley fell ill on the Friday, died on Sunday,
       without, to the astonishment of Madame Elise,
       having previously completed the work in hand. The doctor,
       Mr. Keys, called too late to the death bed, duly bore
       witness before the coroner's jury that "Mary Anne
       Walkley had died from long hours of work in an over-
       crowded workroom, and a too small and badly ventilated
       bedroom." In order to give the doctor a lesson in good
       manners, the coroner's jury thereupon brought in a verdict
       that "the deceased had died of apoplexy, but there
       was reason to fear that her death had been accelerated
       by over-work in an over-crowded workroom, &c." "Our
       white slaves," cried the "Morning Star," the organ of the
       free-traders, Cobden and Bright, "our white slaves, who
       are toiled into the grave, for the most part silently pine
       and die."[6]
       [6] Vol. i, pp. 239, 240.
       Edward VI: A statue of the first year of his reign,
       1547, ordains that if anyone refuses to work, he shall be
       condemned as a slave to the person who has denounced
       him as an idler. The master shall feed his slave on bread
       and water, weak broth and such refuse meat as he thinks
       fit. He has the right to force him to do any work, no
       matter how disgusting, with whip and chains. If the
       slave is absent a fortnight, he is condemned to slavery for
       life and is to be branded on forehead or back with the
       letter S; if he runs away thrice, he is to be executed as
       a felon. The master can sell him, bequeath him, let him
       out on hire as a slave, just as any other personal chattel
       or cattle. If the slaves attempt anything against the
       masters, they are also to be executed. Justices of the
       peace, on information, are to hunt the rascals down. If it
       happens that a vagabond has been idling about for three
       days, he is to be taken to his birthplace, branded with a
       redhot iron with the letter V on the breast and be set
       to work, in chains, in the streets or at some other labor.
       If the vagabond gives a false birthplace, he is then to
       become the slave for life of this place, of its inhabitants,
       or its corporation, and to be branded with an S. All persons
       have the right to take away the children of the
       vagabonds and to keep them as apprentices, the young
       men until the 24th year, the girls until the 20th. If
       they run away, they are to become up to this age the
       slaves of their masters, who can put them in irons, whip
       them, &c., if they like. Every master may put an iron
       ring around the neck, arms or legs of his slave, by which
       to know him more easily and to be more certain of him.
       The last part of this statute provides that certain poor
       people may be employed by a place or by persons, who
       are willing to give them food and drink and to find them
       work. This kind of parish-slaves was kept up in England
       until far into the 19th century under the name of
       "roundsmen."[7]
       [7] Vol. i, pp. 758, 759.
       Page after page and chapter after chapter of
       facts of this nature, each brought up to illustrate
       some fatalistic theory which Marx professes to have
       proved by exact reasoning, cannot but stir into fury
       any passionate working-class reader, and into
       unbearable shame any possessor of capital in whom
       generosity and justice are not wholly extinct.
       Almost at the end of the volume, in a very brief
       chapter, called "Historical Tendency of Capitalist
       Accumulation," Marx allows one moment's glimpse
       of the hope that lies beyond the present horror:--
       As soon as this process of transformation has
       sufficiently decomposed the old society from top to bottom,
       as soon as the laborers are turned into proletarians, their
       means of labor into capital, as soon as the capitalist
       mode of production stands on its own feet, then the
       further socialization of labor and further transformation
       of the land and other means of production into so-
       cially exploited and, therefore, common means of production,
       as well as the further expropriation of private proprietors,
       takes a new form. That which is now to be
       expropriated is no longer the laborer working for himself,
       but the capitalist exploiting many laborers. This
       expropriation is accomplished by the action of the immanent
       laws of capitalistic production itself, by the
       centralization of capital. One capitalist always kills
       many, and in hand with this centralization, or this
       expropriation of many capitalists by few, develop, on
       an ever extending scale, the co-operative form of the
       labor-process, the conscious technical application of
       science, the methodical cultivation of the soil, the
       transformation of the instruments of labor into instruments
       of labor only usable in common, the economizing of all
       means of production by their use as the means of production
       of combined, socialized labor, the entanglement
       of all peoples in the net of the world-market, and with
       this, the international character of the capitalistic regime.
       Along with the constantly diminishing number of the
       magnates of capital, who usurp and monopolize all
       advantages of this process of transformation, grows the
       mass of misery, oppression, slavery, degradation, exploitation;
       but with this, too, grows the revolt of the working-
       class, a class always increasing in numbers, and disciplined,
       united, organized by the very mechanism of the
       process of capitalist production itself. The monopoly of
       capital becomes a fetter upon the mode of production,
       which has sprung up and flourished along with, and
       under it. Centralization of the means of production and
       socialization of labor at last reach a point where they
       become incompatible with their capitalist integument.
       This integument is burst asunder. The knell of capitalist
       private property sounds. The expropriators are
       expropriated,[8]
       [8] Vol. i pp. 788, 789.
       That is all. Hardly another word from beginning
       to end is allowed to relieve the gloom, and in this
       relentless pressure upon the mind of the reader lies
       a great part of the power which this book has
       acquired.
       Two questions are raised by Marx's work: First,
       Are his laws of historical development true? Second,
       Is Socialism desirable? The second of these questions
       is quite independent of the first. Marx professes
       to prove that Socialism must come, but scarcely concerns
       himself to argue that when it comes it will be
       a good thing. It may be, however, that if it comes,
       it will be a good thing, even though all Marx's arguments
       to prove that it must come should be at fault.
       In actual fact, time has shown many flaws in Marx's
       theories. The development of the world has been
       sufficiently like his prophecy to prove him a man of
       very unusual penetration, but has not been sufficiently
       like to make either political or economic history
       exactly such as he predicted that it would be.
       Nationalism, so far from diminishing, has increased,
       and has failed to be conquered by the cosmopolitan
       tendencies which Marx rightly discerned in finance.
       Although big businesses have grown bigger and have
       over a great area reached the stage of monopoly,
       yet the number of shareholders in such enterprises
       is so large that the actual number of individuals
       interested in the capitalist system has continually
       increased. Moreover, though large firms have grown
       larger, there has been a simultaneous increase in
       firms of medium size. Meanwhile the wage-earners,
       who were, according to Marx, to have remained at
       the bare level of subsistence at which they were in
       the England of the first half of the nineteenth century,
       have instead profited by the general increase
       of wealth, though in a lesser degree than the capitalists.
       The supposed iron law of wages has been
       proved untrue, so far as labor in civilized countries
       is concerned. If we wish now to find examples of
       capitalist cruelty analogous to those with which
       Marx's book is filled, we shall have to go for most
       of our material to the Tropics, or at any rate to
       regions where there are men of inferior races to
       exploit. Again: the skilled worker of the present day
       is an aristocrat in the world of labor. It is a question
       with him whether he shall ally himself with the
       unskilled worker against the capitalist, or with the
       capitalist against the unskilled worker. Very often
       he is himself a capitalist in a small way, and if he
       is not so individually, his trade union or his friendly
       society is pretty sure to be so. Hence the sharpness
       of the class war has not been maintained. There
       are gradations, intermediate ranks between rich and
       poor, instead of the clear-cut logical antithesis
       between the workers who have nothing and the capitalists
       who have all. Even in Germany, which
       became the home of orthodox Marxianism and developed
       a powerful Social-Democratic party, nominally
       accepting the doctrine of "Das Kapital" as all but
       verbally inspired, even there the enormous increase
       of wealth in all classes in the years preceding the
       war led Socialists to revise their beliefs and to adopt
       an evolutionary rather than a revolutionary attitude.
       Bernstein, a German Socialist who lived long in
       England, inaugurated the "Revisionist" movement
       which at last conquered the bulk of the party. His
       criticisms of Marxian orthodoxy are set forth in
       his "Evolutionary Socialism."[9] Bernstein's work,
       as is common in Broad Church writers, consists
       largely in showing that the Founders did not hold
       their doctrines so rigidly as their followers have
       done. There is much in the writings of Marx and
       Engels that cannot be fitted into the rigid orthodoxy
       which grew up among their disciples. Bernstein's
       main criticisms of these disciples, apart from such as
       we have already mentioned, consist in a defense of
       piecemeal action as against revolution. He protests
       against the attitude of undue hostility to Liberalism
       which is common among Socialists, and he blunts the
       edge of the Internationalism which undoubtedly is
       part of the teachings of Marx. The workers, he
       says, have a Fatherland as soon as they become
       citizens, and on this basis he defends that degree of
       nationalism which the war has since shown to be
       prevalent in the ranks of Socialists. He even goes
       so far as to maintain that European nations have a
       right to tropical territory owing to their higher
       civilization. Such doctrines diminish revolutionary
       ardor and tend to transform Socialists into a left
       wing of the Liberal Party. But the increasing prosperity
       of wage-earners before the war made these
       developments inevitable. Whether the war will have
       altered conditions in this respect, it is as yet
       impossible to know. Bernstein concludes with the wise
       remark that: "We have to take working men as they
       are. And they are neither so universally paupers as
       was set out in the Communist Manifesto, nor so free
       from prejudices and weaknesses as their courtiers
       wish to make us believe."
       [9] Die Voraussetzungen des Sozialismus und die Aufgaben
       der Sozial-Demokratie."
       In March, 1914, Bernstein delivered a lecture in Budapest
       in which he withdrew from several of the positions he had taken
       up (vide Budapest "Volkstimme," March 19, 1914).
       Berstein represents the decay of Marxian orthodoxy
       from within. Syndicalism represents an attack
       against it from without, from the standpoint of a
       doctrine which professes to be even more radical and
       more revolutionary than that of Marx and Engels.
       The attitude of Syndicalists to Marx may be seen in
       Sorel's little book, "La Decomposition du Marxisme,"
       and in his larger work, "Reflections on
       Violence," authorized translation by T. E. Hulme
       (Allen & Unwin, 1915). After quoting Bernstein,
       with approval in so far as he criticises Marx, Sorel
       proceeds to other criticisms of a different order. He
       points out (what is true) that Marx's theoretical
       economics remain very near to Manchesterism: the
       orthodox political economy of his youth was accepted
       by him on many points on which it is now known to
       be wrong. According to Sorel, the really essential
       thing in Marx's teaching is the class war. Whoever
       keeps this alive is keeping alive the spirit of Socialism
       much more truly than those who adhere to the
       letter of Social-Democratic orthodoxy. On the basis
       of the class war, French Syndicalists developed a
       criticism of Marx which goes much deeper than those
       that we have been hitherto considering. Marx's
       views on historical development may have been in a
       greater or less degree mistaken in fact, and yet the
       economic and political system which he sought to
       create might be just as desirable as his followers
       suppose. Syndicalism, however, criticises, not only
       Marx's views of fact, but also the goal at which he
       aims and the general nature of the means which he
       recommends. Marx's ideas were formed at a time
       when democracy did not yet exist. It was in the
       very year in which "Das Kapital" appeared that
       urban working men first got the vote in England and
       universal suffrage was granted by Bismarck in
       Northern Germany. It was natural that great hopes
       should be entertained as to what democracy would
       achieve. Marx, like the orthodox economists,
       imagined that men's opinions are guided by a more
       or less enlightened view of economic self-interest, or
       rather of economic class interest. A long experience
       of the workings of political democracy has shown
       that in this respect Disraeli and Bismarck were
       shrewder judges of human nature than either Liberals
       or Socialists. It has become increasingly difficult
       to put trust in the State as a means to liberty,
       or in political parties as instruments sufficiently
       powerful to force the State into the service of the
       people. The modern State, says Sorel, "is a body of
       intellectuals, which is invested with privileges, and
       which possesses means of the kind called political for
       defending itself against the attacks made on it by
       other groups of intellectuals, eager to possess the
       profits of public employment. Parties are constituted
       in order to acquire the conquest of these
       employments, and they are analogous to the State."[10]
       [10] La Decomposition du Marxisme," p. 53.
       Syndicalists aim at organizing men, not by party,
       but by occupation. This, they say, alone represents
       the true conception and method of the class war.
       Accordingly they despise all POLITICAL action through
       the medium of Parliament and elections: the kind of
       action that they recommend is direct action by the
       revolutionary syndicate or trade union. The battle-
       cry of industrial versus political action has spread
       far beyond the ranks of French Syndicalism. It is
       to be found in the I. W. W. in America, and among
       Industrial Unionists and Guild Socialists in Great
       Britain. Those who advocate it, for the most part,
       aim also at a different goal from that of Marx. They
       believe that there can be no adequate individual
       freedom where the State is all-powerful, even if the
       State be a Socialist one. Some of them are out-and-
       out Anarchists, who wish to see the State wholly
       abolished; others only wish to curtail its authority.
       Owing to this movement, opposition to Marx, which
       from the Anarchist side existed from the first, has
       grown very strong. It is this opposition in its older
       form that will occupy us in our next chapter.
        
       _____
       Content of PART I-HISTORICAL. CHAPTER I - MARX AND SOCIALIST DOCTRINE [Bertrand Russell's book: Proposed Roads To Freedom] _